NTT to be revised

From Philosophical Vegan Wiki
Jump to: navigation, search


Other old stuff

NTT counterpart sections

Value Narcissism etc

Old steel-manning and interpreting

Getting to the steel-manned version

Isaac Brown

Old summary of issues

Old CounterExample

Part 1 Counterexample

To show Part 1 is invalid we can pose a counterexample in which:

(i) sentient humans have moral value
(ii) sentient nonhuman animals do not have moral value, independent of their traits
(iii) human counterparts have moral value, independent of their traits.

So in this model the following three statements are true:

(i) ∀x ( Hx ⇒ Mx )
(ii) ∀t ∀x ( ( Ax ∧ Tt ∧ ( Pxt ∨ ¬Pxt ) ) ⇒ ¬Mx )
(iii) ∀t ∀x ( ( CPx ∧ Tt ∧ ( Pxt ∨ ¬Pxt ) ) ⇒ Mx )

Checking against the argument;

P1 - P1 is true due to (i)

P2 - If we instantiate x to be animal x*, y to be a counterpart y*, t to be a trait t*, and x* & y* to both lack t*, then P2 takes the form

A ⇒ ¬ ( B ∧ ( C ∧ ( D ⇒ ( E ⇒ F ) ) ) )

Where

  • A:⇔ Ax*
  • B:⇔ Tt*
  • C:⇔ ¬Px*t*
  • D:⇔ CPy*
  • E:⇔ ¬Py*t*
  • F:⇔ ¬My*

In our model we have;

A is true, B is true, C is true, D is true, E is true and F is false (due to (iii)).

So we can now determine the truth of P2:

  1. E ⇒ F takes the form (true ⇒ false) so it is false
  2. D ⇒ (E ⇒ F) takes the form (true ⇒ false) so it is false
  3. C ∧ ( D ⇒ ( E ⇒ F ) ) takes the form (true ∧ false) so it is false
  4. B ∧ ( C ∧ ( D ⇒ ( E ⇒ F ) ) ) takes the form (true ∧ false) so it is false
  5. ¬(B ∧ ( C ∧ ( D ⇒ ( E ⇒ F ) ) ) ) takes the form ¬(false) so it is true
  6. A ⇒ ¬ ( B ∧ ( C ∧ ( D ⇒ ( E ⇒ F ) ) ) ) takes the form (true ⇒ true) so it is true

Hence P2 is true.

C - C is false due to (ii)

Hence we have a case, allowed by the logical form of P1, P2, and C, where P1 and P2 are true, but C is not. Thus the argument is logically invalid.

The reason why we can do this is because the truth of P2 has no bearing on whether or not animals have moral value, as there is nothing in the logical form of the argument that says moral value must be based on a trait (as is the case with the correction) nor is there anything to say counterparts lacking certain traits are animals (as is the case with the alternative interpretation).

(Universal & Existential Instantiation; [1] & [2])

Part 2 Counterexample

Similarly to Part 1, to show Part 2 is invalid we can pose a counterexample in which:

(i) sentient nonhuman animals have moral value
(ii) we are not morally required to not exploit sentient nonhuman animals, independent of their traits
(iii) counterparts have moral value and we are morally required to not exploit them, independent of their traits

So in this model the following three statements are true:

(i) ∀x ( Ax ⇒ Mx )
(ii) ∀t ∀x ( ( Ax ∧ Tt ∧ Mx ∧ ( Pxt ∨ ¬Pxt ) ) ⇒ ¬RNEx )
(iii) ∀t ∀x ( ( CPx ∧ Tt ∧ Mx ∧ ( Pxt ∨ ¬Pxt ) ) ⇒ RNEx )

Checking this against the argument follows the same structure as for the part 1 counterexample, in which P1 & P2 are true and C is false. Rendering Part 2 invalid as well.


Subsequent Verbal Versions of NTT

[Margaret: I think that this section should, discuss, as I suggested above, how "The counterexample shows how, on the natural interpretation, one can accept P1 and P2 but reject the conclusion by accepting something like value narcissism," and that it should go on to "discuss the alternative interpretation of the argument, according to which this counterexample is impossible. Ask Yourself has invoked a principle about traits and identity to argue that for every sentient non-human animal, one has a fully trait-adjusted counter-part which is identical to that animal. We will comment on how this principle is substantive, but can be easily added to the premises of NTT. We will then comment, however, on how the notion of full-trait adjustment in premise 2 makes the argument essentially assume rather than independently establish the moral value of sentient non-humans."


Ask Yourself explains his interpretation of P2 with an animation
Ask Yourself demonstrates his misunderstanding of the law of identity

If we consider the analogy we used earlier, in which we substitute ' humans are of moral value ' for ' I am of moral value ' and demonstrate how NTT would fail to establish moral value in a cow called Bessie. The P2 given by Ask Yourself becomes equivalent to

P2 - A trait-adjusted clone of me with traits identical to Bessie is of moral value

The first problem with this is that this P2 is not the same as the P2 given in the written version. Ask Yourself is incorrectly equating the following two statements:

  1. If a trait-adjusted clone of a human had the set of traits of a (nonhuman) animal it would have value
  2. There is no trait absent in animals which if absent in humans would cause us to deem ourselves valueless.

In the second proposition we are considering traits, which if absent in humans, would make the clone valueless i.e. we are considering all beings with the set of traits; {traits belonging to humans} without {trait(s)} or more simply TH\ {t} not beings with the set of traits of an animal, TA . Now since these beings have a subset of the traits of humans TH\ {t} ⊆ TH, unless the traits of a cow (for example) are a subset of the traits of a human (they are not), the beings can never be cows. This is shown in more detail in the section showing NTT fails for disjoint sets in general.

Note here '\' represents 'without' e.g. {a,b,c,d,e} \ {d,e}={a,b,c}. Adding traits would require the use of the operation 'union' denoted by '∪', with {a,b,c} ∪ {d,e} = {a,b,c,d,e}

Misunderstanding the law of identity

Ask Yourself claims that "two objects with the same traits are the same object" and that "to resist this is to deny the very first law of logic, which is the law of identity". However this is not the case. The first claim is a principle known as the identity of indiscernibles, which says: if for every property P, object x has P if and only if object y has P, then x is identical to y. Or in the notation of symbolic logic:

(∀P)(P(x) ⇔ P(y)) ⇒ x=y.

One cannot use this principle without stating it as a premise. Let's also observe that the law of identity simply states that x is identical to x for each x, it has no use in the context in which Ask Yourself is trying to use it

Switching one trait vs switching all traits

In response to Tierethik und Veganismus' comment, Ask Yourself claims that "If no trait of the animal, switched to the human, would justify devaluing the human, then all traits can be switched without devaluation occurring". However this is not necessarily true. If we assume that we have an infinite set of traits T of which any infinite subset T' is sufficient to grant moral value to a creature possessing traits from T', and possessing infinitely many traits from T is required to have a moral value, then it is true that removing one trait (or replacing a trait with some non-relevant trait) does not cause devaluation, but removing all of them (or replacing all of them with some non-relevant trait)- does.

Confusions and Controversies about NTT's Inavlidity

Ask Yourself thinks it's adequate to dismiss criticisms of his argument made in formal logic

This is not in any way an attempt to obscure the reasoning by using a different language. Ask Yourself responded to the youtuber 'non-ethical vegan' (who tried to provide him with a proof that the NTT argument is a non sequitur by using propositional logic) by claiming that 'This is like Chinese to me, please explain in English'. It is not our task to validate or invalidate such proofs, instead we should recognize the failure of Ask Yourself to accept the validity of the approach. The English language is not suitable to prove or disprove formal arguments. It is however more than enough for informal ones. We already know that FOL (first order logic) is complete and sound, so it is a good candidate for exposing any expressive argument. Failure to translate into FOL will not convince anyone serious about the matter. This also applies for mathematical theorems, most of them are stated in an informal way, but if a peer is not convinced, the job of the mathematician is to dissect the theorem and eventually translate it into FOL. Granted this is not often done (major theorems would be pages long ...), but in the case of NTT it is easy to do so.

Ask Yourself's first defense

Ask Yourself's first defense asserts, in a manner indicating that he doesn't understand literally the first thing about logical arguments (the function of premises), that "arbitrary" can be eliminated as a possibility by (paraphrasing)"feeding it back through the argument" or "trying to plug arbitrary justifications into the argument". While this may follow from his tricky usage of invalid generalizations, or simply his misunderstanding of what a "logical contradiction" means (he thinks it means a double standard), this defense appears to be a form of circular reference, where he tries to support a failed premise by appealing to another unstated variation on that premise (or another version of the argument in entirety) to provide the support it needs.
See Circular References Here for more explanation of this issue.


The Brick Analogy

(defending against non sequitur criticism)
The "Brick" analogy is one he gives as a defense, attempting to show how the need for his version of consistency is grounded in objective reality and doesn't need to be supported by a premise.

It goes as follows:
Ask Yourself attempts to explain why his argument is not a non sequitur
If you're saying that a creature has moral value and you can't distinguish that creature from can't distinguish another creature from that creature in a way that would if true of the first cause you to say it doesn't deserve to have moral value then you're contradicting yourself by actually suggesting that that second creature does not deserve value as well. So if that's too complicated for you to understand you can just do it with physical objects, OK so: I can(n't) lift brick A um there's no difference between or no trait you know present in uh brick B which if true of brick A would make it possible for me to lift brick A so therefore it's contradictory to suggest that I can lift brick B. Well of course that's true. And if there were such a trait if brick B could be lifted then whatever makes it liftable if you map those traits over to brick A then you could lift Brick A too. So this is just a basic formula to discover contradiction.

It is not actually a contradiction in the strict logical sense for it to be the case that (i) I can lift brick A, (ii) there is no difference between brick A and brick B, and (iii) I can't lift brick B. There is nothing in the logical form of these propositions that makes it the case that they can't all be true together. Indeed, it seems conceptually possible for (i) and (ii) to be true and (iii) to be false - if the world did not work according to anything like the physics of our world, it could simply be a basic fact about the universe that you could lift brick A but not brick B.

Add something about how this changes when you bring in the identity of indiscernibles

[Margaret: I'm worried about the old reasons 2 and 3 to reject the brick analogy. I have moved these sections and made some notes on this in the getting to the steel-manned version page]

Logical Contradiction Meaning

Ask Yourself seems to believe "logical contradiction" means the same thing as a double standard. His followers have claimed this more explicitly, and he regularly uses this example to dispute claims like "human" as the source of moral value (paraphrasing):
"What if aliens came to Earth to eat Humans because they aren't aliens, would that be OK? Would you give in and let them eat you, or resist them? If you would resist, you're contradicting yourself."

Claims like these indicate double standards, but they do not indicate contradictions:

1: It is wrong to kill a human
2: It is not wrong to kill an animal
3: It is wrong for an alien to kill a human

Doing something to others based an an arbitrary reason (like your species) and opposing others doing that based on a similar reason is a double standard, but it is not a logical contradiction. A logical contradiction requires a direct negation. For example, any of these claims would create a contradiction with the set above:

1. It is right to kill a human
2. It is wrong to kill an animal
3. It is right for an alien to kill a human


An arbitrary moral assertion without objective substantiation can easily promote double standards because most people don't like being treated like that, and while it is without substantiation it is not a logical contradiction; you can even arbitrarily assert a moral system AND further assert that it's the only true moral system and all others are false. Is this unreasonable? Yes. But is it a logical contradiction? No.
To put this in context of the alien example Ask Yourself likes to use: "If aliens came to the Earth and killed you based on their arbitrary morality, would you be OK with that?" the response it simple, "No, because they are wrong and I am right. My arbitrary morality is absolute true universal law, and theirs' is false."
Ridiculous? Yes! A logical contradiction? No.

Ask Yourself either does not understand the definition of a logical contradiction, or he chooses to ignore the actual definition substituting in his folk definition instead. Ask Yourself believes, or claims to believe, that folk definitions of technical vernacular are perfectly fine to use in a philosophical context even if they completely rewrite the rules of logic and argumentation in the process; if that's the case with this substitution, this is not only malpractice, it's transparent intellectual dishonesty; a pseudo-philosophy of the worst kind, a conscious twisting of definitions as incredible as the pseudo-scientific machinations of Deepak Chopra.
Once you have so flippantly thrown out the fundamental rules and definitions in philosophy and substituted in your own custom "logic" for the real thing, there's just no arguing the case. Ask Yourself wholly rejects logic and supplants his own creation to justify his fallacious arguments, and intentional or not, the result is deception.

What's worse is that beyond holding these incoherent folk definitions, Ask Yourself also commits straw-man fallacies and mischaracterizes his opponent's argument by generalizing claims like "humans" vs. "animals" to "species" to make them appear more in contradiction, but this is not valid:

Defending the Premises of the First Part of NTT

Independence from Substantive Ethical Premises

Ask Yourself claims this argument works on the basis of essentially no substantive ethical premises other than (1) one's view that one is of value - as manifest by one's resistance to being killed - and one's (2) conviction that one would not lose value if one were to lose any of the traits that one currently has but (sentient) animals lack - as manifest, it seems, by one's simply wanting not to be killed if one were to lack those traits.

If true, that would be extremely impressive - particularly if one were committed to valuing oneself simply in virtue of one's having a desire / propensity to resist being killed. It might be the most impressive argument created for anything in philosophy, let alone veganism. As is often the case, if something seems too good to be true it probably is.

Unfortunately this desire for a one-size-fits-all argument has led him to an argument that fails in so many ways it achieves a state of fractal wrongness -- outlined in issues. The attempt to dispense with dependence upon substantive premises found in other normative arguments in order to create the best argument ever has instead resulted in what is at best a failed attempt to dispense with such premises (which ends up looking a lot like the argument from less able humans / "marginal cases") and what is at worse an extremely unconvincing argument. Some speculate that his rejection of corrections and insistence in his argument's soundness in its present form is a consequence of that monomaniacal focus on independence from substantive ethical premises (others may attribute it to general arrogance and refusal to admit to errors of any kind).

However, calling something independent doesn't make it so. The way he uses this argument and the way it's *supposed to* work (despite its non sequitur and other fallacies) demonstrates a series of hidden premises. And while some of these hidden premises Ask Yourself agrees with -- even claiming a few are just definitions -- he doesn't realize the substantive ethical implications of these hidden premises, and how they contradict his own claimed positions.

For his part, on a personal level Ask Yourself claims to be a moral subjectivist (specifically an "ontological subjectivist, and an epistemological objectivist"), his definition of these terms is colloquial and incorrect in the context of philosophy because it generates contradictions and false dichotomies of its own (see objective-subjective distinction), but where it really stands out as a problem is its conflict with the substantive ethical assumptions necessitated by #NameTheTrait (if it is to function in any capacity the way he believes it does), and more specifically a conflict with his own deontological views).

Brief outline of necessary substantive ethical assumptions:

  1. Rejection of value on the basis of arbitrary traits. Obviously P2 needs another premise to function, although Ask Yourself believes some kind of circular reference is adequate instead.
  2. Assertion of the view that non-arbitrary traits must be traits such that, if one were to lack them, one would be willing to agree that one would lack moral value. This may be functionally because he believes a double standard is a "logical contradiction"
  3. Assertion of one's having moral value, and one's having it even if one were to lack certain traits. He does not seem to realize that one could desire to be treated in a certain way even if one did not have value that would give others good reasons to treat one in that way. E.g. he seems to have overlooked the response 'I don't have moral value; you'd be justified in killing me, it's just that I reasonably don't want that to happen - much like, if we were in a chess game, and you were about to check-mate me, you'd be justified in doing that, but I'd reasonably want that not to happen.' In practice, this may be due to his denial of valid dissonant actions, but can also be derived from his brick analogy.
  4. Assertion of deontological moral evaluation due to assertions of P2 in the second part of the argument.

Beyond his actions and claims which clearly indicate these positions, the mere fact that Ask Yourself believes that it is possible to construct any kind of persuasive and logically valid normative argument outside a specified meta-ethical system should be demonstration enough.

Dissonant Actions

In practice, Ask Yourself demands certain responses (on pain of being accused of "logical contradiction") must result from considering oneself to have no moral value. He demands such specific responses that he thinks permits him to accuse people of contradiction on the basis that they might dare to defend their own lives if (for example) attacked by aliens.
However, this is not necessarily the only viable outcome from "lacking moral value", and as explained above under Meta-Ethical Independence it has some serious implications.
In a logical argument, all potentially controversial terms and claims must be properly established by premises, not hidden. Moral value only equates to self defense if you link it to personal value in general by definition, which is begging the question.

It's possible that Ask Yourself doesn't even understand that people can accept something as ethical but still not do it (as though ethical normative forces were absolute). This is ALSO not a "logical contradiction"; it means people have multiple values that compete for behavior, and the most ethical option doesn't always win.
Even if we believed aliens were in the right to come to Earth and eat us, that doesn't mean we wouldn't try to save our lives despite that. Even if we believed resisting were morally wrong, resisting would not be a contradiction: it would only indicate what most people will already admit: we are not 100% moral with no regard for self preservation. Most people will do some otherwise pretty immoral things by their own admission to save their own lives.
It also doesn't mean we'd be in the wrong to save our own lives. People usually don't claim farmed animals are in the wrong for resisting, so these actions may not even be dissonant at all based on a more complex definition of moral action (one that nothing in the argument's premises rebuts). This doesn't even require a double standard.
To make that line of "would you resist the aliens?" reasoning work and accuse contradiction with carnism if people answered in the affirmative, a premise would have to be added to alter the argument, defining "consider ourselves valueless" clearly in behavioral terms as "not try to defend our own interests". And of course that really narrows down the meta-ethics the argument applies to, and from there is is by no means meta-ethically independent.


Invalid Generalizing

In practice the way Ask Yourself tricks some people in debates is by taking what they say and twisting the wording just enough to seem to mean the same thing, but slyly generalizing it so as to create the appearance of not being a trait exception.
For example, by replacing an arbitrary fiat of human value with something about the victim of an offense being of a different species: "Are you OK with being eaten by aliens?" is a common reply.

Ask Yourself is either ignoring or not understanding that the claim that the value is "humanity" is absolute; the aliens are wrong according to that, the value given is not "is a different species". He tries to generalize the statements like that, by saying "species" instead of specifically "human species", to create the appearance of a contradiction where none existed (because it was only double standard, not a logical contradiction)

The deformation of arguments committed by Ask Yourself is a form of straw manning.
When an opponent says:
1. It is wrong to kill a human based on species
2. It is right to kill an animal based on species.
This is a double standard, but it is not a logical contradiction. Ask Yourself follows this by asserting something like: "You contradict yourself by saying it is not ok to kill Y based on X and then deploy it as ok to kill Y based on X", and he is making a generalization of the argument that is nowhere to be justified. It is not allowed to have a deduction rule of the type:

∀x: H(x) -> ¬K(x) ⊢ ∀x: ¬K(x)

∀ : for all
H(x) : x is human
¬ : not
K(x) : ok to kill x based on <insert any justification here>
⊢: entails

That is to say, you cannot have a deduction rule of the type; for all x, if x is human then it is not okay to kill x based on some justification, entails for all x it is not okay to kill x based on the same justification. You can't generalize the argument because it has been constrained to the set of humans. And the follow up argument of " please differentiate human and animal ... " doesn't apply because nowhere in the argument is it said that if you can't differentiate then the treatment should be the same.

It's possible that in doing this Ask Yourself knows what he's doing and is trying to play word games and misrepresent people's answers to trick them, but whether he's doing it accidentally or intentionally the outcome is the same: it's intellectually dishonest, and he continues the practice despite being alerted to these problems.


Circular References

(Or infinite regress)

Ask Yourself attempts to explain why his argument does not require improvements or modifications
Of course not all Christians use circular arguments like this, but it's common enough to make a useful analogy to Ask Yourself's reasoning

NameTheTrait is a non-sequitur as stated, but rather than correct the argument Ask Yourself has employed some very bad arguments supporting it which only commit him more strongly to a varied assortment of fallacies.
None are more transparent or easy for the layman to grasp than his seeming circular references.

In short, Ask Yourself claims you don't need any additional premises to require justification at all, much less to require justification by a non-arbitrary trait for P2, because P2 creates those premises:

P2 - There is no trait absent in animals which if absent in humans would cause us to deem ourselves valueless.

And according to him, this is because you can take something like "arbitrary value" or "fiat" and just (paraphrasing)"feed it through the argument" to show a contradiction. "You wouldn't accept arbitrary so you can't use arbitrary" (something he only allows if you would "accept" it)
In this way, by referring to an alternative version of the failed premise itself, this is comparable to the common theological circular reference to prove god from scripture and scripture from god, e.g. justifying the existence of God by referring to the Bible, and giving the Bible authority because it's God's word as demonstrated by the Bible. (#NotAllChristians, of course)
A more precise analogy that indicates more clearly the absurdity of the #NameTheTrait claim is this one:

#NameTheTrait vs. #NameTheVerse*
Argument: #NameTheTrait #NameTheVerse
Formula: P1 - Humans are of moral value

P2 - There is no trait absent in animals which if absent in humans would cause us to deem ourselves valueless
C - Therefore without establishing the absence of such a trait in animals, we contradict ourselves by deeming animals valueless

P1 - Humans are of moral value

P2 - There is no verse absent in the Bible needed to deem God's exclusive right to dictate infallible moral law
C - Therefore without establishing the absence of such a verse in the Bible, we contradict ourselves by deeming Christianity untrue.

Missing Premises: P3 - Such a trait can not be arbitrary

P4 - Moral value must be justified by such a trait.

P3 - A moral-giving God actually exists

P4 - The Bible is the infallible word of said God

Response: No you f*cking retard, just feed it back trough the argument.

There's no trait absent in animals that would let you use arbitrary to devalue them that if absent in humans would make you accept arbitrary devaluation. It's so obvious you idiot.

You're mistaken beloved friend, just feed it back through the argument.

There's no verse absent in the Bible that would be needed to prove it deems God's moral giving nature, existence, and infallible word as the Bible. Please join us in prayer.

  • Note that no Christians actually use a #NameTheVerse argument, this level of transparently bad logic is not to be found among even the worst apologists.

If Ask Yourself was trying to write P2 in a way that made it recursive and generalized the rule by removing it from subjective context, he failed at doing so. This is NOT how the premise is written, and it obviously does not achieve this if you plug in arbitrary traits provided they are worded clearly; it's still a non-sequitur, and doesn't provide an out to arbitrary answers to the claim there's no trait allowing arbitrary (a potential infinite regress).
It's also important to note that IF the premise actually were written like this, it would be a lot easier for people to disagree with directly. As it is, like in the theist example, P2 is relatively non-controversial for most people because it's merely a fact statement (for example, about what is written in the Bible, or about animal physiology).

The issue with the theological version is probably more obvious: in order to be true, a claim about the Bible being true or saying anything with absolute credibility (like that god wrote it) must be premised by an assumption that such a God exists and actually wrote the bible in the first place (and didn't lie, and knew what he was talking about, etc.). Without that premise to start with, the argument fails and can not substantiate itself (i.e. by referring back to the existing unfounded assertion that the Bible is true).

With #NameTheTrait, likewise, in order to function in the first place P2 must be premised by certain claims that we need to justify moral claims at all (to stop it from being a non sequitur) and further that they should be justified by non-arbitrary traits (to make dismissal non-trivial).
If such premises were included (as in the corrected versions), the argument would not need to be self-referential for support, and without them it can't provide that support to itself because this golden rule/anti-double standard aspect Ask Yourself claims never manifests. As it stands, the argument only makes the assertion that you wouldn't consider yourself valueless if you lacked a trait lacking in animals, which is not relevant. This may create a double standard, but a double standard in itself is not a logical contradiction, and nothing in the argument establishes the meta-ethical relevance of that (such as by making assertions of fairness or justice in morality). To equate a double standard to "logical contradiction" is an extreme misunderstanding of the meaning of logical contradiction explained here.

Ask Yourself claims that is it not the specific arbitrary claim that must be compatible with P2, but a generalized form, as such this fallacy could be partially explained by his invalid generalizing, but this does not seem to be the whole of the story because these self-referential claims go beyond that to dismiss the need for the supporting premises necessary to make P2 function at all (although this could in part be explained by his radical misunderstanding of the Meaning of "logical contradiction").

Meaning of "moral value"

"Moral value" has no clear meaning or material implications. This is easy to fix, as noted above: it just needs to be grounded in some meta-ethical premise.

Unfortunately, Ask Yourself is unwilling to do this (and has even removed grounding from previous informal versions of his argument) seemingly because he believes it is the subjectivity of this provision that makes the argument work for subjectivists. He thinks it's up to whatever "you" think gives moral value, and you just have to be "logically consistent" with that. And if he actually abided by that, his argument would have no normative persuasive power at all.
In practice, it's this ambiguity in the argument he uses to manipulate his opponents, supplanting his own unique definition of consistency/contradiction to relate to double standards in imposing your will upon others in ways you wouldn't want to be imposed on. Instead of being honest enough to just put that in the argument as a premise (as recommended above) he changes the rules of logic itself and the very definition of "logical contradiction" to suit his agenda.

Obviously, in philosophy a "logical contradiction" is not the same thing as a double standard. See Logical Contradiction Meaning for more info on this.


Earlier Informal Versions

Reddit discussion of an earlier, superior version of the argument with a very different first premise

It's important to note that in an earlier informal version of this argument, Ask Yourself used to premise the argument with a claim like "Either you believe actions must be justified, or you don't", allowing that his argument only applies in the former case: this served as an appropriate premise (given a reasonable definition of justification) grounding morality in that justification and functionally forbidding arbitrary standards. It was a much better argument in the past. The formalized version he later presented discards this essential premise in an ill-conceived attempt to make the argument apply to subjectivists and relativists as well, but breaking the argument in the process; for more on this see Meta-Ethical Independence Here.

It's not clear if the fact that earlier and less formal versions were logically superior is some kind of vindication of Ask Yourself, or actually makes this all the more ridiculous because he supposedly spent time and effort changing these arguments to make them logically invalid. He started as an outlier among vegan youtubers, making fairly compelling arguments and being relatively personable, and has reversed course entirely. It may be inevitable that the disjoint correlates to his growing fandom; with cult-like adoration often comes a failure to engage usefully with criticism.
Analogies can be found in hollywood[3] where fame can lead to overconfidence, as well as in modern politics where political echo chambers promote polarization and sabotage useful bipartisan policies[4]. Something to think about, but it was important to note that this was not always the case and why.

It's possible that Ask Yourself is uniquely resistant to reason and criticism, but that's too easy of an excuse because this can also represent a failure on our part (as the skeptical side of the vegan community) to engage with criticism sooner before he became so invested in these arguments (he now believes #NameTheTrait is responsible for his youtube success, and seems to believe admitting any flaw in it or revising the argument to correct those flaws would destroy him).


[Margaret: I've moved the old sections here on 'All Humans', 'Existential Meaning', and 'All/Some Animals' to the getting to the steel-manned version page; with sections of the same names: All Humans, Existential Meaning, and All/Some Animals.


[Margaret: I *think* that the old 'P2 Inconsequential' has been incorporated into the discussion of NTT's invalidity above. However I've moved the old section to the getting to the steel-manned version page to preserve it.

[Margaret: I've moved 'Ask Yourself's first defense' into the above section on confusions and controversies about NTT's invalidity.

The Second Part of NTT

The second part of the argument fails in the same ways the first part does, in addition to:

Value Spectrum

The first part of the argument, if corrected, might establish animals have some value, but does not establish equal value in part one. Part two then attempts to take that spectrum of value and convert it into an absolute: non-exploitation. It should convert a spectrum of value into a spectrum of acceptable exploitation, from no value = total exploitation fine to fully functioning human level value = no exploitation acceptable. Logically, animals like cows would lie somewhere in between where some exploitation would be acceptable, while their interests would also have to be considered somewhat to limit that exploitation (i.e. animal welfare, which already exists and does not necessarily conclude in veganism).

Pt2 P2 Empirically False

P2 in the second part is also just outright empirically false for the vast majority of people in two ways, and in addition causes issues in debates due to perceived hypocrisy, depending on how you look at "exploitation":

The action or fact of treating someone unfairly in order to benefit from their work. -Oxford English Dictionary[5]

The distinction hinges on "fairness"; in a general universal sense of denying the fairness of bad luck or ensuring the arrangement is legitimately in the interest of all of those being used, or based merely on the rules laid out in law by society?

A. In the general sense

Nothing short of non-exploitation is considered adequate? Incorrect.

P2 - There is no trait absent in animals which if absent in humans would cause us to consider anything short of non-exploitation to be an adequate expression of respect for human moral value.

The absolutist language is a serious problem here, but it's also the only thing that ties in strict veganism without taking the care to present any empirical argument.
Only a minority of people (largely Marxists) oppose any measure of human exploitation in principle, and people (even most Marxists) certainly don't show agreement in actual practice - we literally consider it an adequate (not ideal, even if just tolerable for some) compromise every day we accept it and function in society rather than abstaining in protest.

If you want to dilute the definition of "inadequate" to include some far-off goal of changing it without any meaningful abstention in the present, then most meat-eaters are already vegan by the same standard that armchair Marxists are already political revolutionaries despite eating meat and working an ordinary 9-5 respectively.

Is that the standard we're after?
Is all you have to do to be vegan is find animal agriculture troubling in some abstract way, imagine some day it will all be different, and post a couple things on Facebook about it?

If not, obviously P2 fails by virtually any trait, because we already DO consider something "short of non-exploitation to be [...] adequate".

You could argue that it's more practical to go vegan than to abstain from capitalism, but some rare people can and DO make efforts to do the latter so it's obviously not impossible to work at it. However, this argument is not about practicality at all: it's about extremes. It's about non-exploitation, not limited exploitation to the extent we find acceptable because it benefits society as a whole (like regulated capitalism, for those of us non-Marxists) -- that would come back to the welfare issue and lead into an empirical argument about whether the exploitation of animals is justified by the overall benefit to society (I don't think it is, but nothing in the #NameTheTrait argument presents that and Ask Yourself doesn't even think it's a valid question to ask).

It's not clear if Ask Yourself (a vehement "anti-SJW") would be personally willing to bite the bullet on that one and accept Marxism and radical Social Justice as co-implications of making this premise work, and admit that they are equally necessary along side veganism.
Given how often he has spoken against hitching veganism to social justice, it seems unlikely he would switch sides on that one and take the intersectional approach just to defend this formulation of #NameTheTrait.

Either way, even if all of the other problems in this argument were fixed or ignored, the inclusion of this premise inherently excludes all but Socialist Social Justice advocates. And given Ask Yourself's primary audience and outreach is to "anti-SJWs", it's a fatal flaw in the argument's utility.


B. In the narrow sense

(The narrow sense of playing by the rules of society)

Some of these rules are absolute and we do not accept violations of them, but they are based on social contract, NOT on expression of human moral value.

For example: According to social rules, it's wrong to steal a million dollars from a billionaire who hoards or wastes it (which would be an "exploitation" the billionaire didn't consent to) in order to save the lives of hundreds of people.
It's even wrong to harvest the organs of a dead person who no longer needs them to save a dozen lives unless the person consented to be an organ donor.
It's also perfectly acceptable to target people you know are not financially responsible to offer them credit cards, and then garnish their wages to milk them indefinitely for the minimum payment on that TV they didn't need.
All in the rules of the game.

Exploitation only occurs in this sense when a contract is violated or laws are broken.
Rules of legal justice are not there because they are morally right in every instance, but because of the social utility; because we, as members of the social contract, value our own consent and property rights over total harm. They're ultimately self interested.

These bounds are not there because people don't want to be unduly exploited, e.g. contract law, no human trafficking, etc.

Ask Yourself would argue that if you don't want to be bought and sold (by somebody from another culture where you're in the out-group, or an alien), that creates a contradiction if you would permit others to be (based on #NameTheTrait) unless there's a trait that separates you and the others that if true of you would make you OK with being bought and sold.
Again, #NameTheTrait is not a valid argument. It doesn't contain premises that forbid arbitrary distinctions, and it doesn't contain premises that necessitate naming traits (it only meaninglessly claims there isn't one). Appealing to another iteration of a broken argument in order to fix holes in the same broken argument doesn't work. Just saying there isn't a trait is fundamentally different from claiming moral value must be justified by such a trait, and different again from claiming that behavior like this which isn't even linked to moral value must be justified by one regardless of moral value.

If an alien bought and sold you, then of course that would be against your social rules which are engaged in to protect humans, and human society would fight the aliens because humanity is self interested. Not wrong, just against the rules of human society. The alien society and the human society might, by treaty, come to terms where they agree not to buy and sell each other, and by this means the social contracts would be unified and it would become a violation of the rule (exploitation) to use an alien like that. The idea that two distinct social contracts (not morality) could be at odds with each other when they serve different populations is not a contradiction.

While there are some vegans involved in an intersectional vegan form of social justice who would disagree (And I would be surprised to learn that after all of his criticism of "SJW"s Ask Yourself is one), the fact of people buying and selling cows does not seem in any readily apparent way to increase the chances of you being bought and sold. Empirically, justice does not seem to be an every sentient being or none game, and at least most people don't think it is one.

This would make the second part of P2 irrelevant:

P2 - There is no trait absent in animals which if absent in humans would cause us to consider anything short of non-exploitation to be an adequate expression of respect for human moral value.

And it would either mean that animal agriculture is not exploitative because it is permitted by the arbitrary rules of society with certain limits on welfare (just as slavery would not have been exploitation before abolition; it was your bad luck to be born a cow or a slave), or outside of legal bounds it would mean "exploitation" of animals is meaningless because they have no status in the game by which to evaluate whether they are or are not being exploited according to the narrow definition of social contract.

Either way (ignoring the fact that the whole argument is a non sequitur), if the trait being asked for is meant to justify why forms of exploitation that would not be acceptable for humans are acceptable for animals in the general sense or why the same actions ARE exploitation for humans and not for animals, the social understanding would provide just such a trait P2 claims doesn't exist: Societal Membership Status.

This is not a basis for morality or moral value at, but it is the basis of societal rules and if that's what you're basing actions on then none of this is even a double standard.

--

This is obviously not an issue with the validity of the argument (a false premise doesn't mean the logic is wrong), but it is a serious issue with the soundness. Also, when a premise is this obviously incorrect for the vast majority who don't hold absolute views it creates problems for the perception of the argument (you might as well include a premise about the Earth being flat).
If Ask Yourself were willing to embrace intersectional social justice, he might actually get pretty far with this argument within that limited circle, but it's counterproductive for the internet and society at large where people don't generally agree with the politics.

But even if we restricted the argument to social justice advocates who will be most inclined to agree on those points of justice, and even if we added in the necessary premises to make this P2 and the P2 from the first argument function, and fixed all of the other problems, you're still left with the fact mentioned above of the gradient of moral value. The only "fixing" of this argument to avoid that is to either normalize moral value by somehow asserting all beings of moral consideration have the same moral value, or by ignoring it completely and normalizing outcome despite drastic differences in moral value (which obviously makes the spectrum of "moral value" irrelevant).
Neither of those outcomes are desirable unless you're trying to create an army of fundamentalists who consider exploitation or murder of an insect as severe an infraction as that for a human being because they both have an interests.

C. Issues in debates

Hypocrisy does not mean somebody's point is wrong, but it does in practice makes people unlikely to consider the advice or condemnation of an apparent hypocrite due to the seeming dishonesty and lack of sincerity suggested by actions at odds with claimed beliefs.

Vegan Gains defends his use of supposedly exploitative products

These issues have actually been problematic for Vegan Gains in debates, who has professed to agree with NTT. When posed with questions such as 'Was exploitation involved in the production of your phone, if yes, why do you not boycott such products?', his answer usually takes the form; yes exploitation was involved, but I need them for my activism, income and youtube videos, and is not immoral for me to do so. All of these are good reasons, however it shows that he does not consider the absolute of 'nothing short of non-exploitation' to be an adequate expression for human moral value, as pragmatic considerations take precedence. And if pragmatic considerations take precedence, then it's an empirical cost-benefit analysis, and not an absolutist argument like this that is useful.

An example of this was during the Warski debate, in which, on the subject of technology Vegan Gains stated 'you can justify some amount of exploitation in that sort of area of your life'. Ask Yourself was Vegan Gains's partner in this debate and it's fair to say that he agreed.


A similar issue arises when posed with questions such as 'Do you avoid all things produced using animal products, or products that may contain trace animal products e.g. glues etc.?'. Again the answer is no, and it that it is not immoral for me to do so. Which, similarly, means that he does not consider the absolute of 'non-exploitation' to be an adequate expression for animal moral value.

It's worth noting the definition of veganism used by most vegans, including Vegan Gains, is

'A philosophy and way of living which seeks to exclude—as far as is possible and practicable—all forms of exploitation of, and cruelty to, animals for food, clothing or any other purpose; and by extension, promotes the development and use of animal-free alternatives for the benefit of humans, animals and the environment. In dietary terms it denotes the practice of dispensing with all products derived wholly or partly from animals.'

which is not absolutist in nature.

Fans of Ask Yourself may think you can resolve such issues using the golden-rule, by answering 'yes' to the question 'would you accept the exploitation if you were the victim in these cases?'. There are two issues with this:

I. This would not be relevant, as the argument as framed requires the absolute of non-exploitation. The argument could be rewritten (and Ask Yourself seems to think other variations can be substituted on the fly in discussion) to separate various categories of exploitation (for food, for other products, etc.), but even if so:

II. It seems at least very unlikely that people would be willing to be killed to make glue to bind books, etc. When in practice Ask Yourself demands this kind of assent to validate any action, it fails because nothing is likely to justify requiring our deaths short of some dramatic heroic sacrifice (some people might be willing to die to cure cancer, although it seems unlikely that a cow would be concerned with this and be willing to make that noble sacrifice).
Ask Yourself or Vegan Gains can try to make the distinction between products (for which the animal was actually killed) and byproducts (for which the animal was not killed), and claim the latter is not exploitation because the animal has already been killed and a corpse can not care. Again, there are two issues with this:
1. It would mean that once the primary product was identified (e.g. beef), all other products would be vegan, from gelatin to leather to brain, organ meats, bone broth, etc. Possibly even quite a few processed meats, all of which are to various degrees byproducts.
2. The product-byproduct distinction is actually a spectrum, not a dichotomy. All products that are sold contribute to the profit motive to raise and kill the animal; they are all reasons to do so, and use of byproducts subsidizes the primary products to make them cheaper and push them into the market just as consumption of primary products subsidize the byproducts. There's no fundamental, categorical difference between use of glue as a binder and eating a steak; they're differences of degree of exploitation.

Given these considerations, it's clear that Ask Yourself's answers don't resolve the absolutism demanded by this argument. In accordance with this, everybody would be engaged in "logical contradiction" (if the argument were valid). And because logical contradiction itself is not a spectrum (see principle of explosion), either you're logically consistent or you have a contradiction, and that makes everybody equal with respect to the only normative compulsion of this argument (for those who want to avoid "contradiction"), from the most obsessive of personal purity vegans to the most ravenous carnist. If there is no distinction between the two, the argument has no normative force at all, and it has no utility to anybody (even if we fixed all of the other problems).


[Margaret: I'm moving the subsections on Independence from Substantive Ethical Premises, Circular References, Invalid Generalizing, and Dissonant Actions to the section on #Defending the Premises of the First Part of NTT

[Margaret: I'm moving the Logical Contradiction Meaning sub-section to the section on [[#Defending the Premises of the First Part of NTT; since this and the foregoing cleaned out the 'In practice, and with defense of the argument' subsection except for the part on personal contradictions which looks relevant to the second part of NTT, I'm eliminating that dedicated subsection: BUT I think that we should include as many examples from in practice and in debates as possible in other sections to explain the importance of the points being made and how they are relevant to effective advocacy.]]


Personal Contradictions

Herein Ask Yourself rejects Utilitarianism and by implication consequentialism generally, asserts deontological rights-based moral reasoning
Ask Yourself's deontological arguments in #NameTheTrait and his recent deontological claims are at odds with his personal claims to believe in a value spectrum.

He has for some time claimed to believe that animals exist on a spectrum of moral value from the least to the most, which could be plotted on a rising curve relative to sentience (or something like that). He has claimed that the vegans who assert equal value for all animals are irrational and make other vegans look bad. Both of these are sensible claims, and the images he has produced to illustrate these claims are clear and depict a moral system that very much favors rational value-based calculations.

Hierarchy2up.png

However, recent comments and the second half of the #NameTheTrait argument indicate a very different perspective on moral evaluation.

The problem people typically have with consequentialism is usually in being short-sighted: they have looked at some of the immediate consequences, but have ignored systemic and long-term consequences, or have generated a false dichotomy and failed to examine alternatives.

Ask Yourself expounds his rejection of (and misunderstanding of) consequentialism in more (grusome and sexually disturbing) detail:

yeah I reject just absolute consequentialism as any thinking rational person should okay if you are a pure consequentialist then you would have to accept a ton of absolutely barbaric nonsense so for example if you can save five people's lives by killing one against their will and harvesting their organs you'd have to say that that is ethical if a bunch of guys raping a girl is going to generate more well-being for them than its gonna generate suffering for her maybe they roofie her or something like this you would have to say that the ethical thing to do is to rape her so if you don't accept those kind of situations then you're not a pure consequentialist
Ask Yourself's own fans understand consequentialism better than he does.

In the "rape" case, the answer should be incredibly obvious: Not raping, and doing something else for enjoyment which is win-win, is the preferable course of action, just as eating food that has a lower harm footprint is vs. eating meat.

This is apparently what Ask Yourself thinks consequentialist morality looks like, in his perverted thought experiment:

  • Don't do anything at all: 0
  • Gang rape without roofies: -1,000,000 for the girl, + 50 for the men (10 each) = -999,950
  • Gang rape with roofies (where the girl never knows, the men are very gentle, and she just has a worse hangover): -10 for the girl +50 for the men = +40

Ask Yourself understands only that the second option isn't good, but he thinks it's OK to set up false dichotomies and consider anything "in the green" to be acceptable to consequentialists while ignoring better options:

  • Don't do anything at all: 0
  • Gang rape without roofies: -999,950
  • Gang rape with roofies: +40
  • Go home and watch porn and masturbate: +50 for the men

Clearly the fourth option (which Ask Yourself ignores) is preferable to any gang raping options.
Even a hedonistic utilitarian (arguably the worst kind of consequentialist) understands that he or she should choose the fourth option, because the third does more harm by comparison to a reasonable alternative on offer.
And if the men had some kind of psychological problem where they could only "get off" by raping? Then the sensible option is to seek therapy to fix that problem long term, again reaping more overall benefit.
In consequentialism, unlike deontology, actions are not wrong in themselves, so you can adjust these scenarios with more and more outlandish hypotheticals (up to having the world blow up if they don't rape) to favor the gang rape, but at a certain point the situation is no longer realistic and it no longer informs practical behavior.

The problem being expressed by Ask Yourself is an intellectually unsophisticated representation of the Utility Monster (an extreme scenario where utilitarianism arguably breaks down), but it's a problem that doesn't exist in day to day reality or cause issues with any of the common moral dilemmas present in society.

It's also worth mentioning that classical hedonistic utilitarianism doesn't have a monopoly on consequentialism.
There are also preference utilitarians, where the girl's strong preference to not be raped (even without her knowing it) factors in making that negative regardless of the men's attempts to mitigate her physical distress, just like our preference to not be killed painlessly and unexpectedly factors into our own moral value.
Likewise, not all consequentialists are Utilitarians of any stripe; there are also altruistic consequenitalists who do not regard their own pleasure as a reason to harm others.

The Organ issue is more complicated assuming those people will genuinely die without organs (although we have to ignore the practical problems of incompatibility).
Obviously we don't accept a numbers reasoning for humans due to the greater consequences of violating social contract, the utility of rights agreements between human beings, and the aspect of personal risk (which is selfish and not moral in nature); All things non-human animals are not part of. For animals, it's pure moral consideration in terms of net violation of interest, which is why we can and must look at numbers of comparable instances of harm (not for lack of considering quality as well).
If we were looking a socially removed case of consequentialist triage without any other options, and minus all practical problems, it absolutely makes sense to kill one to save five if those five each have the same value as the one.

Does Ask Yourself switch the track? It's not clear based on his deontological reasoning. He wouldn't want to be killed because somebody switched the train to his track, so he couldn't do it, right?

The classical Trolley problem proposed by philosopher Philippa Foot, for instance, proposes exactly this where there are no other alternatives. In brief:
There is an out of control trolley on a track, and if it continues it will kill five people who are working (or tied up) on the track. There is a switch to switch the track to another where the trolley would kill only one person on that track. Do you pull the switch or not? There is no other way to save those five people, and the one will certainly die if you do.

The consequentialist answer of "switch the track" is overwhelmingly favored by both the layman and the philosopher in surveys.
However, this is not a situation typical of the every day reality we live in.

Which would Ask Yourself do? Based on his categorical-imperative style heuristic, it seems like he would not switch the track:

I don't think it's ethical for people to rape a girl if it's gonna generate more well-being for them because I don't want to be raped if it's gonna generate more well-being for the rapist no I don't think it's ethical to steal someone's organs against their will to save five people because I don't want my organs stolen against my will to save five people so yes I'm not a raw consequentialist

He wouldn't want somebody to switch a train track to make a train run over him to save five other people from the same fate, so he couldn't do it to others.
He pays no mention in this heuristic to what the other FIVE people would want (Would he want somebody to switch the track AWAY from him, saving his life and four others and killing somebody else?).

Whether you agree with consequentialism or not, you can't have it both ways. Ask Yourself , indicative of his ignorance of philosophy, repeatedly claims that consequentialism can be a form of deontology based on his definitions despite the fact that they are regarded as opposing.

"within the domain of moral theories that assess our choices, deontologists—those who subscribe to deontological theories of morality—stand in opposition to consequentialists." -SEP[6]

Consequentialism does not call acts in and of themselves wrong, but looks at the consequences of those acts. Deontology does the opposite: actions are right are wrong in and of themselves, the actual consequences don't matter.
Rule consequentialism is a heuristic adopted because of its consequences, not a true hybrid approach.
Redefining deontology outside of the modern philosophical context to call it simply "rules", and explaining that a rule could be to "do what provides the best consequences" is a retort that proves only personal ignorance of the topic.

Regardless of whether consequentialism or deontology are correct, the issue is that, due to those perceived problems (which are not actually problems for consequentialists) Ask Yourself has thrown out consequential reasoning in favor of the deontological rights-based approach to morality.

And in that deontological context he has created, it's hard and to justify saying this is a sound basis for preferential moral action (which he implicitly does in his value hierarchies):

  • 1 human > 1 pig

Or:

  • 1 pig > 1 dog
  • 1 dog > 1 mouse

Or even:

  • 1 human > 1 mouse

When you reject this as a sound basis for preferential moral action:

  • 3 humans > 1 human

Once you throw out numbers, you are throwing out the most meaningful part of value quantification; Ask Yourself may claim it's a spectrum, but he's acting as if it's a straight line.

There is a strain of deontological reasoning which resolves these contradictions by claiming hierarchies where value differences are absolute, but that within a single level comparisons can't be made.
For example, they would claim that a single human is worth more than an infinite number of lower value animals, and in this case that a pig is worth more than an infinite number of animals lower than it.

However, this makes relative value meaningless (it's of no use to say a being is half as valuable compared to another: it is infinitely less valuable), and if you recognize value spectrum among humans (as Ask Yourself likely does since he rejects arbitrary species boundaries) you also have to recognize that one human with an iota more moral value than another due to slightly higher sentience is worth more than an infinite number of all humans with an iota less value. This is a position Ask Yourself probably doesn't hold, thus thus the contradiction with his own beliefs.

Correction

WIP

Argument for sentient animal moral value:
P1 - Sentient Humans are of moral value (or at least one is oneself of moral value, although as pointed out in the section on Independence from Substantive Ethical Premises, this actually goes beyond one's simply wanting to defend one's personal interests)
P3 - Arbitrary assertions of moral value are not acceptable, moral value must be justified by some relevant non-arbitrary trait.
P4 - In order to be relevant and non-arbitrary, a trait must be one that would cause us to deem ourselves valueless if we lacked it.
P2 - There is no trait absent in sentient non-human animals which if absent in sentient humans would cause us to deem ourselves valueless.
C - Therefore, Sentient non-human animals are of some moral value (not necessarily equal to humans)
Argument for veganism from animal moral value:
P1 - Sentient Animals are of moral value.
P2 - Current animal agriculture practices are harmful to their moral interests.
P3 - Current animal agriculture practices are also harmful to human moral interests: Environmental harm (which harms humans too) Resource waste (in developed countries) Zoonotic plague source Antibiotic resistant bacteria
P4 - Benefits of current animal agriculture practices are small and limited to avoiding short term inconvenience in the developed world. (Markets adapt, tastes change)
P5 - The morality of actions is dependent on the consequences of those actions in terms of the moral harms and benefits that result. (I.E. consequentialism)
P6 - Morality is other directed, not selfish (I.E. Altruistic) Personal pleasure is not a moral justification for causing harm to others.
P7 - In the developed world, purchasing and supporting the production of most animal products has net negative consequences for others.
P8 - Nobody is perfect, but a good person is the kind of person who aspires to do better and works on becoming a better person day by day.
C - Therefore, if you are a moral person, it is a moral imperative to work on moving away from consumption of most animal products and toward plant based staples (with the ultimate and non-exclusive consumer goal of going "vegan" or "ostrovegan")

Conclusion

Note how the corrected argument establishes the necessary meta-ethical assumptions to make the argument itself valid (Rejects subjectivism, establishes Universalism based on the Golden Rule, rooted in behavioral qualities to avoid existential ambiguity or dependence on subjective value claims).

Naturally for every premise introduced the potential audience the argument can appeal to is reduced (because they have more premises to reject), but failing to do so creates a non sequitur which reduces the audience of competent logicians to zero.

A bad argument for veganism can occasionally trick reluctant people into temporarily accepting it, but this only works as long as that person is under your control (in a cult setting this can be effective). As soon as the person shares these reasons with friends and family, it becomes vulnerable to any number of counterarguments which demonstrate the holes in its logic. For a bad argument, being shared more broadly makes it less effective rather than more.

The apparent strength of #NameTheTrait is that it is worded in such a confusing way using double negatives and a conclusion which isn't straight forward (rather than saying animals have moral value, it makes redundant claims about contradiction) that it's difficult for most people to immediately recognize the fallacious logic. However, most people don't have to recognize the problems: one person has to. At this point, dozens have, independently citing different problems with the argument. An invalid argument is never a strong argument in a free speech environment. Just as bad theistic arguments come on the internet to die, so do bad arguments like these. The end result is only to make vegans look irrational and/or dishonest in a way comparable to theistic apologists who make poor arguments for god (such as the ontological argument).

Debunking bad arguments for veganism helps to make sure vegans are using good arguments that will stand the test of time and reduce recidivism, as well as buys good will from carnists who may be encouraged to reconsider their beliefs that vegans are dishonest and take into consideration the good arguments for veganism and may move them to reducetarian practices.