Difference between revisions of "Less Able Humans"

From Philosophical Vegan Wiki
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 1: Line 1:
Since no one seems to have filled this in, here is a version. It is a slight adaptation from the slides of a philosophy professor who has given permission to use them. He teaches this as an argument for the Principle of Equal Consideration, then allows that even if we weaken that substantially, the case for veganism follows from empirical reality: <br>
+
Since no one seems to have filled this in, here is a version. It is a slight adaptation from the slides of a philosophy professor who has given permission to use them. He teaches this as an argument for the Principle of Equal Consideration, then allows that even if we weaken that substantially, the case for veganism follows from empirical reality. <br>
 +
 
 +
Many carnists assume that, although we have strong moral reasons not to harm (and to benefit) humans, we lack (at least in many contexts) strong moral reasons not to harm (or to benefit) non-human animals. The most natural attempts to justify this assumption invoke certain intellectual abilities that typical human adults have and non-human animals lack, such as abstract reasoning ability, the ability to think about ethics, the ability to enter into agreements, moral agency, etc. The basic idea of the argument from less able humans (aka "marginal cases") is that these justifications fail, because there are many sentient humans who lack these fancy intellectual abilities, but we have still have strong moral reasons not to harm (and to benefit) them. The only other potentially relevant difference between these intellectually less able humans and non-human animals, but when we distinguish bare biological species membership from its typical psychological accompaniments, we can see that it is simply something like ability to interbreed and produce fertile offspring, shared history of phylogenetic descent, or gross morphology. But these bare biological or historical features are as obviously irrelevant to our basic moral reasons not to harm or to benefit someone as her her gamete size or chromosomal configuration (sex) or her skin color, hair texture, and facial features as a result of her ancestors' area of ancestry (ethnicity or race). So we really should conclude that, just as lesser intellectual ability does not make the well-being of intellectually less able humans in itself less morally important than ours, lesser intellectual ability also does not make the well-being of non-human animals in itself less morally important than ours.
 +
 
 +
It is important to clarify what it means to deny that someone's well-being is not "in itself less morally important" than ours in virtue of her lesser intellectual abilities. This is not to
  
  
Line 5: Line 9:
  
 
P1. Some humans (infants, young children, profoundly intellectually disabled) are intellectually comparable to non-human animals <br>
 
P1. Some humans (infants, young children, profoundly intellectually disabled) are intellectually comparable to non-human animals <br>
P2. If the well-being of non-human animals (e.g. their avoiding a given amount of suffering, their benefiting from a given quality of life) is morally less important than ours (in virtue of these lesser intellectual abilities), then the well-being of these humans is equally less important (in virtue of their lesser intellectual abilities) <br>
+
P2. If the well-being of non-human animals (e.g. their avoiding a given amount of suffering, their benefiting from a given quality of life) is in itself less morally important than ours (in virtue of these lesser intellectual abilities), then the well-being of these humans is in itself equally less morally important (in virtue of their lesser intellectual abilities) <br>
P3. But the well-being of these humans isn’t morally less important than ours
+
P3. But the well-being of these humans isn’t in itself less morally important than ours
 
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
 
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
 
Therefore, C1. The well-being of non-human animals is not morally less important than ours <br>
 
Therefore, C1. The well-being of non-human animals is not morally less important than ours <br>

Revision as of 04:36, 18 November 2017

Since no one seems to have filled this in, here is a version. It is a slight adaptation from the slides of a philosophy professor who has given permission to use them. He teaches this as an argument for the Principle of Equal Consideration, then allows that even if we weaken that substantially, the case for veganism follows from empirical reality.

Many carnists assume that, although we have strong moral reasons not to harm (and to benefit) humans, we lack (at least in many contexts) strong moral reasons not to harm (or to benefit) non-human animals. The most natural attempts to justify this assumption invoke certain intellectual abilities that typical human adults have and non-human animals lack, such as abstract reasoning ability, the ability to think about ethics, the ability to enter into agreements, moral agency, etc. The basic idea of the argument from less able humans (aka "marginal cases") is that these justifications fail, because there are many sentient humans who lack these fancy intellectual abilities, but we have still have strong moral reasons not to harm (and to benefit) them. The only other potentially relevant difference between these intellectually less able humans and non-human animals, but when we distinguish bare biological species membership from its typical psychological accompaniments, we can see that it is simply something like ability to interbreed and produce fertile offspring, shared history of phylogenetic descent, or gross morphology. But these bare biological or historical features are as obviously irrelevant to our basic moral reasons not to harm or to benefit someone as her her gamete size or chromosomal configuration (sex) or her skin color, hair texture, and facial features as a result of her ancestors' area of ancestry (ethnicity or race). So we really should conclude that, just as lesser intellectual ability does not make the well-being of intellectually less able humans in itself less morally important than ours, lesser intellectual ability also does not make the well-being of non-human animals in itself less morally important than ours.

It is important to clarify what it means to deny that someone's well-being is not "in itself less morally important" than ours in virtue of her lesser intellectual abilities. This is not to


The Argument from Less-Able Humans ("Marginal Cases")

P1. Some humans (infants, young children, profoundly intellectually disabled) are intellectually comparable to non-human animals
P2. If the well-being of non-human animals (e.g. their avoiding a given amount of suffering, their benefiting from a given quality of life) is in itself less morally important than ours (in virtue of these lesser intellectual abilities), then the well-being of these humans is in itself equally less morally important (in virtue of their lesser intellectual abilities)
P3. But the well-being of these humans isn’t in itself less morally important than ours


Therefore, C1. The well-being of non-human animals is not morally less important than ours


This entails (if you like in conjunction with P4. Our well-being is morally important) the Principle of Equal Consideration: human and non-human animal well-being is of equal intrinsic moral importance (i..e moral importance in itself and apart from its further effects) - e.g. all else held equal, the fact that an act would inflict a given amount of harm (e.g. a given amount of suffering) on a human or a non-human animal is an equally strong moral reason against it.

Defense of P3: It is deeply implausible that intellectual ability affects the intrinsic importance of one's well-being once we distinguish (i) its role in making one a moral agent who owes duties vs. a moral patient who is owed duties, (ii) its role in affecting the instrumental importance of one's well-being for others, and (iii) its role in determining how beneficial or harmful certain things are for you (including how much typical human adults benefit from living vs. how much non-human animals and profoundly intellectually disabled humans benefit from living).

Defense of P2: The only relevant thing that distinguishes non-human animals from intellectually comparable humans is bare biological species membership, but it's deeply implausible that bare biological species membership is relevant to the intrinsic moral importance of someone's well-being once one we focus on what it really is: something like potential to interbreed to produce fertile offspring, psychology-independent morphology, phenotype-independent genotype, history of phylogenetic descent. It's no more plausible that these matter to the intrinsic moral importance of someone's well-being than someone's ethnicity / continent of ancestry and consequent facial features, hair texture, and skin colour (race), or her chromosomes and relative gamete size (sex).

The weakening: Even if somehow intellectual ability or biological species memebership per se mattered to the moral importance of someone's well-being they couldn't matter very much. Since they seem utterly devoid of moral importance; surely it is safe to at least conclude:


C2. Principle of Minimal Consideration: We should / are morally required to avoid inflicting enormous harm on non-human animals for what is at most relatively trivial benefits for ourselves.


Empirical considerations about factory farming, human health, environmental effects, and, if you like, further philosophical considerations about what makes death a harm, the potential relevance of the fact that future farmed animals won't exist unless we buy animal products, and the probabilities that one's purchasing decisions will make a difference of various kinds and to what extent this matters, we get:


P5. To avoid inflicting enormous harm on non-human animals for what is at most relatively trivial benefits for ourselves, we must be vegan.


Finally, C2 and P5 entail:


C3. We should / are morally required to be vegan.