Exmly wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 9:28 am
Thank you guys! I've read it all and it gives me much more to work with. No I wouldnt identify as a consequentialist but I'm gonna work on the "life is most important to life" strategy.
I don't think any of us know who that guy is, but his arguments are proximal to deontology if that's really what you're looking for.
However, I strongly advise against it. With deontology you're building a foundation on sandy ground and it won't hold up to careful scrutiny.
You may want to read this topic:
viewtopic.php?t=785
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 am
Theories of indirect rights have nothing to do with relativism.
Of course it's cultural relativism. It's about the opinions of people, not derived facts of moral necessity.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 am
Indirect rights aren't based on the "subjective opinion" of people but instead derived from the rights of others. Children are seen as patients of society at large so their rights can be seen to be derived from the society at large not just the guardians.
A bold claim. Then let's see the derivation rather than assertions.
Read esquizofrenico's reply.
esquizofrenico wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 2:13 am
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 12:56 am
You don't have to bite that bullet for two reasons. Firstly indirect rights aren't just derived from the guardians but society as a whole. Also denying an entity direct rights doesn't mean the entity should be treated however you wish. Laws that protection a class of people or animals aren't inconsistent with a denial of rights from these groups.
The only other possible consideration you can have about something if it doesn't have rights is with respect its relationship with other beings that have rights. All moral obligations can be reformulated in terms of someone's right. So I think that at the very least you would have to accept that rules about mentally ill people or animals are because aesthetic or utilitarian reasons, if they have not direct rights. You could say: People should not torture animals/mental ill people because some people do not enjoy watching animals being tortured, or because it is generally bad for society when those things occur. But those kind of rules fail to give solid moral obligations on a personal level, if I personally do not get affected when I torture mentally ill people and I do it in the privacy of my home, I should not care about either of those arguments.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amSocial contract theories aren't necessarily deontological, we are discuss deontology here.
The attempts at objective theory that are based on it? Yes they are, so was Rand's (although she hated Kant).
You can consider social contract within a utilitarian framework for its instrumental value to social order, but that's not what the OP wants help with.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amWithin that framework, there is no reason why denying rights to some group would force you to accept that you can treat that group however you wish.
Within a consequentialist framework, no. Within a deontological framework, yes it does: the only thing that matters is direct rights violations, though the heavens may fall.
You can't appeal to consequences within a deontological system.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amThis is why I brought up indirect rights
Care to bring square circles into this too?
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amits way one of explaining why non-rights holders would have some protections in a deontological system.
No, they have protection on the basis of being property of the rights holders IF and ONLY IF the rights holders want them to have those protections.
If the parent saying "sure, you can eat my kid for $5" then you can eat the kid for $5 (you don't have to do it, but it's not wrong to do it).
If you don't understand that, you don't understand deontology or deontological social contract theories. Protection (not inherent rights) is only granted by actual rights holders.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amI agree....but you're the one discussing it. I haven't brought it up once.
I see, you just think deontology includes cultural relativism (and consequentialism, apparently), but don't realize it.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amWhy does denying rights force one to accept "anything goes" treatment for non-rights holders?
It's just how deontology works.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amAgain, that is the point of theories of indirect rights.
If you want to talk about cultural relavtivism or some trademarked mishmash of consequentialism and deontology, please start a new thread.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amYou need to argue that any theory of rights MUST accept "anything goes" for non-rights holders.
No, I don't. That's an issue of definition. If you want to go off on a tangent and argue that deontology isn't deontology (which I might even agree with, since deontology isn't logically consistent in itself) then you should start a new thread. There are all kinds of holes you can poke in it, which is why I don't recommend deontological arguments.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amThis is much different than humans using a toilet, we do that for specific reasons and those reasons can be understood where as a dog doesn't understand the reason they shouldn't poop on the floor of your house. They do it merely because they've been trained.
Most humans poop in toilets because they have been trained to, not because they understand the nuances of sewage management and sanitation.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amBut we are discussing moral thinking, dogs do not reason morally. Humans clearly do.
While most humans probably *can* reason morally if taught to, most humans clearly do not bother or think about it.
So do those humans who have not and do not think about it lack moral consideration?
If so, that's about as arbitrary as requiring humans to know calculus for moral consideration.
If that's your arbitrary moral basis and you think that's OK there's not much I can say about it, but it's as sensible as people who advocate that anybody who can't compute limits can be enslaved, killed, eaten, whatever, and you'd have no basis to criticize such people for enacting their system except trying to shout at them that you like your system better.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amthey very clearly do starting at around 2~3 years old.
They start to have empathy, that doesn't equate to moral reasoning unless you're claiming empathy IS moral reasoning, in which case many non-human animals do that as well.
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amIts funny, you always seem so hell-bent on attacking/insulting me yet I'm not even discussing my personal views.
Every claim you make is a personal view. Here, whether or not your subscribe to it,they are your views about deontology (which are very confused, although deontology itself is very confused so that is
kind of understandable).
carnap wrote: ↑Tue Apr 24, 2018 11:54 amThe OP wants a good deontological argument for veganism but part of that is going to be understanding the common objections one may give.
There's no
good deontological argument for anything. The only arguments you can make are showing how deontological arguments against veganism are bad and hoping the person defaults to the opposite in attempt to conserve some illusion of consistency.