When nature won’t stay still: Conservation, equilibrium and control by William M Adams

General philosophy message board for Discussion and debate on other philosophical issues not directly related to veganism. Metaphysics, religion, theist vs. atheist debates, politics, general science discussion, etc.
Post Reply
User avatar
NonZeroSum
Master of the Forum
Posts: 1159
Joined: Fri Feb 10, 2017 6:30 am
Diet: Vegan
Location: North Wales, UK

When nature won’t stay still: Conservation, equilibrium and control by William M Adams

Post by NonZeroSum »

_____________________________

In summary:

Bill Adams explores some of the implications of the growing discourse about non-equilibrium ecology for conservation. He argues that a deeper understanding of the complex processes involved in ecosystem change can give humans a new sense of control over nature, particularly visible in the rise of restoration ecology.

Adams, William H (Bill)
Bill Adams is Reader in the Geography of Conservation and Development at the Department of Geography, University of Cambridge, UK. He has written several books,including Future Nature: A Vision for Conservation(Earthscan,1996) and Green Development: Environment and Sustainability in the Third World (Routledge, 2001). He is interested in conservation and rural change, especially in Africa and the UK, and has served on the councils of the Cambridgeshire Wildlife Trust, the British Association for Nature Conservationists and Fauna and Flora International.


_____________________________

When nature won’t stay still: Conservation, equilibrium and control

William M Adams


_____________________________

FIELD WORK


Two memories suggest themselves to me. In the first, I am standing on the slope of a rounded limestone hill in southern England, looking south across a huge vista of woods and fields, the rolling lowlands of the Kentish Weald. Near at hand there is thin grass with the little bumps of ant hills, and on the hilltop the remains of a Bronze Age earthwork approximately 3500 years’ old. One or two of my fellow students are on their hands and knees, peering excitedly through hand lenses at grasses and flowers, and uttering the shrill squeaks of the conservationist at play. To our right lies what looks like a battlefield, a sea of hawthorn stumps and the ash mounds that marked the sites of small, hot fires. We are on a National Nature Reserve (NNR), a Site of Special Scientific Interest (SSSI), and this was the result of careful scientific conservation management. [1]

The reserve was famous for its chalk grassland plants and insects; but this ‘natural’ diversity was, in fact, artificial. Chalk grassland, I was being told, was human-made, an ‘anthropogenic ecosystem’, ‘semi-natural’ vegetation. In the intense agricultural and urbanized landscape of south-east England, nothing remained of the mix of vegetation communities that must once have existed on the unoccupied chalk and clays left at the end of the last glacial maximum 10,000 years ago. As the climate shifted, and plants and animals and eventually people arrived, the landscape changed, and ‘natural’ vegetation was forced to change with it. Under tens of centuries of human management, plants and insects that could thrive on the nutrient-poor limestone of the chalk hills, and cope with the inexorable nibbling of countless generations of sheep, accumulated in wonderfully diverse assemblages in what ecologists during the 20th century came to call chalk grassland.

I was told that human action had destroyed the ‘natural’ post-glacial vegetation. However, in its place anthropogenic activity had created a diverse, new vegetation assemblage in which a multitude of plants and insects found a foothold. In time, this, too, began to disappear. People had long ago cleared and ploughed almost all the rest of the chalk downland in southern England (especially during the period since World War II), and the chalk grassland species, presumably once common, were now rare. As a result, the whole of a much wider heritage of natural diversity was invested in this fragment of human-created sward. That is why it was a nature reserve.

However, even in a nature reserve it seemed that nature could not be left to itself.In this environment,chalk grassland was not a stable equilibrium vegetation community. Left alone, this grassy paradise would slowly turn into a dull, species-poor scrubland and, eventually, woodland. The only way to keep the diversity of grassland species was to stop vegetation succession. Conservation management was needed in order to hold back the tendency of nature to restore the natural balance. Since World War II, chalkland sheep-grazing had become uneconomic, the grassland had become rougher, and the scrub moved in – hence, the need to cut and remove the scrub in order to reset the clock of ecological succession at the stage with maximum species richness.

A second memory occurs a couple of years later and far away. I am peering through the windscreen of a Land Rover in northern Nigeria at a patch of bare soil, surrounded by scrubby trees. The screech of acacia thorns against the body work has mercifully stopped, and we are in an area of totally bare land in a clearing in the grazing reserve through which we have been driving. It is long after the rains and blindingly hot. We get out to inspect vegetation and soil. At some time in the past, people have cleared and cultivated this land. The lines of the cultivation ridges are still visible, but the soil has sealed over and the surface is mirror hard. Nothing grows now, not even weeds. The acacia trees have failed to recolonize. The land seems irrevocably spoiled. My companion is kicking the toe of his shoe against the hard surface, muttering and shaking his head.

A few kilometres on, we stop again in a new clearing in the thin forest. This time we find a small stockade of cut thorn branches with a large white bull inside. It is part of a Fulani pastoralist camp; but there is nobody about. The bull is tall and rangy, but surprisingly sleek. A pile of green branches has been cut for fodder, for on the dry, grey earth there is only a faint suggestion of wispy grass stems. On the edge of the clearing, small, scrubby acacia trees have been half-cut through quite recently and their green leaves eaten; others have been cut to make the small stockade. This seems like the scene that must logically precede the one before, where the healthy forest is being cut by unwary people, eventually to be farmed and spoiled, and abandoned. We talk about the processes that seem to be going on, the probability that the grazing reserve is slowly being destroyed by overgrazing. We eventually drive away, the Land Rover still protesting at the thorns.

At the time, these experiences seemed to offer classic morality tales. On the chalk hills of England, careful conservation management was needed to maintain the diversity of nature against its own powers of deterioration. In Nigeria, on the edge of the Sahel, management was required to stop people from destroying the environment. There were too many people in the wrong place, trying to grow crops on degraded soil and exhausting the soil, or cutting trees to feed livestock because the grassland was overgrazed. At that time, in the aftermath of the ‘Sahel drought’ of the early 1970s, the problem of desertification was a hot topic of debate in seminar rooms and learned journals. To me, conditioned by the literature on drought and human-induced desertification in the Sahel, it was easy to build in my mind a scenario for the future of these places. It was one of environmental degradation, with the natural vegetation progressively transformed by people and their livestock, the natural productivity of the land destroyed by unsustainable land use, the balance of nature upset by human action. It did not occur to me that this interpretation might be wrong. It did not (at least, not then) occur to me to wait until the bull’s owner returned to see what he thought was happening in that hot place. [2]


________________________________________

THE BALANCE OF NATURE



The balance of nature is a powerful symbol. It was the single ‘Big Idea’ that underpinned the environmental revolution that began during the 1960s in Europe and North America, and which progressed in various ways and at various speeds until the 1990s, when it was mainstreamed by the 1992 Earth Summit in Rio. There was a ‘balance of nature’ that humans had disrupted. This certainly seemed self-evident to me through my childhood (trekking to Alexandra Palace in London to see the National Nature Week exhibition in 1963, or watching television pictures of the oil tanker Torrey Canyon, aground and burning on Seven Stones Reef between Land’s End and the Scilly Isles in March 1967, and being bombed by the navy and the air force, while leaking Kuwaiti oil onto the Cornish coast). [3] To a child, the evidence was plain: nature was precious and under threat, it had found its own balance and this was being upset. People, in their greed and technological arrogance, were disrupting the balance of nature. As a basic environmentalist route-map to the ills of the late 20th century, the idea of nature in balance served me well enough for a long while, providing the oxygen for more late evening conversations and arguments with friends than I care to remember.

These ideas are as deep as the history of environmentalism (Grove, 1992; 1995). One need look no further than George Perkins Marsh’s Man and Nature (1864):

Nature, left undisturbed, so fashions her territory as to give it almost unchanging permanence of form, outline, and proportion.

…whenever the Indian, in consequence of war or the exhaustion of the beasts of the chase, abandoned the narrow fields he had planted and the woods he had burned over, they speedily returned, by a succession of herbaceous, arborescent and arboreal growths, to their original state. Even a single generation sufficed to restore them almost to their primitive luxuriance of forest vegetation (Marsh 1864, pp 29, 30).

Marsh’s theme was clear: nature established an equilibrium and humans disrupted it. This simple idea was still providing the take-home message of Rachel Carson’s Silent Spring, the proof text of Western environmentalism and the sound bite of countless television documentaries and Walt Disney animal movies 100 years after Marsh’s writing. [4] It reflects, too, ideas that ran through the science of ecology. When this was in its infancy, during the late 19th century, shortly after Marsh was writing, it took on board a powerful, organic metaphor of nature, a view of nature balanced and integrated and threatened by change from ‘outside’, from human action (Botkin, 1990; Livingstone, 1995).

The idea of a balance of nature continues to be seductive and to have a powerful appeal for environmentalists, in general, and conservationists, in particular. However, during the last decade of the 1990s, it began to be challenged by other ideas that suggest a more complex approach to understanding ecosystem change. These ideas allow nature much more dynamism and variability. No longer can the gendered image of rapacious human and passive equilibrial nature be accepted comfortably. [5] Using two case studies, this chapter describes the implications of this change for conservation in understanding nature. The first is the semi-arid lands of Africa, both the classic terrain of ‘big nature’ (the ‘big five’ and savanna national parks) and the home ground of African pastoral people. The second is the more domestic scale of small nature reserves in the densely packed and intensively managed rural landscape of the UK. Although, at one level, very different, common ideological currents run through conservationist thinking. In both cases, a challenge to the dominant mode of understanding nature as balanced and threatened offers radical and challenging opportunities for conservation action. First, however, let me explain what I mean by the ‘ecology of equilibrium’.


_______________________________________

THE ECOLOGY OF EQUILIBRIUM



During the first decades of this century, nature was portrayed by the emerging science of ecology as, essentially, rather static, an array of habitat fragments as natural objects. In this thinking, ecology drew (like conservation) on the strength of amateur natural history and the Victorian mania for collecting (Allen, 1976, Griffiths, 1996). The links between ecology and conservation in industrialized countries were very close. In Research Methods in Ecology, the American ecologist F E Clements provided a scientific basis for identifying vegetation ‘types’ (Clements, 1905; McIntosh, 1985). In the UK, Arthur Tansley drew on the work of amateur botanists to write the classic Types of British Vegetation (Tansley, 1911), and provided both a classification of vegetation and a framework for the first lists of proposed nature reserves in the UK (Sheail, 1976; Adams, 1996). When Clements developed ideas about plant succession, he suggested a process of continuous change towards a ‘climatic climax’. He likened the ‘vegetation formation’ to a complex organism ‘developing’ through time. This way of understanding ecological change drew deliberate analogies with the growth of individual organisms (Clements, 1916).

These ideas of vegetation as organism were subsequently challenged by Harold Gleason and by Tansley; but ecology’s dependence upon the organic metaphor survived. In 1920, Tansley argued against the idea that all aggregations of plants had the properties of organisms, and in 1935 he published a sharp critique of Clementsian thinking about the climatic climax (McIntosh, 1985). He suggested that succession involved complex patterns, with soils, physiography and human action all driving change in different (but specific) directions under different conditions. To capture this complexity he framed the new concept of the ecosystem (Tansley, 1935; 1939; Sheail, 1987). In time this, too, came to be understood as a balanced system whose components meshed and integrated to create equilibrium through negative feedback.
The development of increasingly sophisticated theoretical and experimental approaches to ecology eventually led to a more mechanistic framework of analysis. This was based upon Tansley’s concept of the ecosystem, to which the analysis of ecological energetics and, subsequently, systems analysis were applied (Tansley, 1935; Lindemann, 1942; McIntosh, 1985; Botkin, 1990). However, although the science of ecology developed in scope and sophistication, historians of ecology argue that the fundamental notion that ecosystems tended towards equilibrium endured (McIntosh, 1985; Worster, 1994). The classic ‘equilibrium paradigm’ in ecology dominated ecology until the 1970s (Steward et al, 1992). Ecological systems were closed, and ecosystems were self-regulating so that, if disturbed, they would tend to return towards an equilibrium state. This paradigm, in turn, fed ideas in the wider environmental movement, underpinning the notion that there was a balance of nature easily upset by inappropriate human action.

During the second half of the 20th century, when both ecosystem management, development planning and conservation were all becoming established in government planning, ecologists mostly portrayed nature as a kind of homeostatic machine (Pahl-Wostl, 1995). Nature was seen as a system whose state was maintained by processes of internal feedback; but it was also susceptible to external control. In fact, ecosystems were analysed as if they were ‘19th-century machines, full of gears and wheels, for which our managerial goal, like that of any traditional engineer, is steady-state operation’ (Botkin, 1990, p12). Human action could upset the delicate working of the machine; but, fortunately, the ecologist could diagnose the problem and (potentially, at least) work out how to put the balance right. Ecological science could therefore be used to generate technocratic recipes for managing nature. Ecologists coined words and concepts drawn from thermodynamics and engineering (such as system, energetics, equilibrium, feedback, balance and control) to describe nature. Conservationists, schooled in ecology, saw themselves in some senses as ‘engineers of nature’ (Livingstone, 1995, p368).

Ecological science also offered a series of ‘natural’ subdivisions of nature. This is the fruit of a desperate desire to classify, dating back to the origins of taxonomy (see Chapter 2 in this book). The arbitrary distinction between species and subspecies are universally accepted, although modern genetic techniques may prove to have some surprises for those conservationists whose programmes are dependent upon these categories. Attempts to provide a taxonomy at larger scales (habitat, ecosystem or vegetation community) are graced by convention, but are less satisfactory. These ‘natural’ units are quite clearly social constructs, whether or not they carry the imprimatur of Two-Way Indicator Species Analysis (TWINSPAN) (Hill, 1979) and the reliable algebra of the National Vegetation Classification (Rodwell, 1991). [6] The attempt to classify the turbulent diversity of nature is based upon assumptions of equilibrium. Only if nature stays still can science get a long enough look at it to provide a usable classification. In that nature is not still, science has to work as if it is. Nature is therefore treated as dynamic, but tending to equilibrium – diverse, but open to simple classification that is robust enough to be useful.


___________________________________

CONSERVATION AND EQUILIBRIUM


Ideas of ecosystem equilibrium have been highly influential for conservation in the temperate environment of the UK. For British conservationists, it was for almost all of the 20th-century axiomatic that nature not only had to be reserved, but also managed within those reserves. Ecological ideas about ecosystem succession demonstrated nature’s own capacity to change in undesirable ways. Awareness grew of the capacity of nature itself to cause change that could bring about the loss of valued features of a reserve (for example, a rare species), particularly through ecosystem succession. As nature conservation became an accepted form of land use in the UK, after the end of World War II, conservationists had to establish rules for reserve management, and for this it drew upon ecological science.

Conservation needed science, and science needed conservation. It was believed that effective reserve management demanded ‘deep scientific knowledge’ of ecosystems: ‘paradoxically, we can ensure the survival of wild places of Britain only by finding out what happens when we interfere with them’ (Nicholson, 1957, pp26, 19). In 1964, Pearsall argued that ecological research required large nature reserves for experiments ‘large enough to allow [for] repeatable assessments of the systems or processes under investigation’ (Pearsall, 1964, p8). Some ecologists were reluctant to accept that wildlife communities might need to be managed (Duffey and Watt, 1970); but conservation demanded an interventionist approach in order to control nature.

Conservation adopted ecology’s language (system, equilibrium, balance, succession, competition, climax), and drew upon it to explain vegetation succession and to prescribe management treatments. In due course, ‘management by interference’ (Nicholson, 1957, p19) became the standard model and also, arguably, the distinguishing feature of British conservation (Henderson, 1992).

Woodwalton Fen in Cambridgeshire provides one example of the emerging need for intervention management. Until the mid 19th century, Woodwalton Fen was undrained, lying adjacent to the open water of Whittlesey Mere. In 1851, this last fenland mere was drained and reclaimed, Woodwalton Fen peat was dug and parts were cultivated. In 1910, it was purchased by a wealthy visionary, the banker Charles Rothschild, as a nature reserve. This purchase, of course, did nothing to stop the rapid plant succession taking place (Nicholson, 1970). By 1959, when the reserve was leased to the Nature Conservancy, about 90 per cent of it was covered with birch or sallow scrub. Many of the species for which it was originally famous had died out, or were close to doing so. The wetland had become a wood, standing like turf on a beach – a tuft of wet woodland, stranded by the drainage of the surrounding farmland that stretched as flat as a pancake away to the level line of the horizon, far away to the north-east.

Conservation of the fen’s fauna and flora seemed to demand decisive intervention. Ecological knowledge directed conservation action to control ecosystem succession, and a programme of clearance, followed by cattle grazing, was begun. It was argued that ‘detailed ecological knowledge’ would be required to maintain the vegetation in the forms that gave the fen its conservation interest (Duffey, 1970, p595).

Although the basic principles of managing wildlife habitat are, today, widely known and taught (see, for example, Green, 1981; Sutherland and Hill, 1995), when conservation was established institutionally during the 1940s, little research had been done. Knowledge of either the need for ecosystem management, or of how and when to intervene in order to maintain the desired characteristics of ‘seral, plagio or sub-climax ecosystems’ (Green, 1981, p178), was rudimentary, at best (Sheail, 1995). New knowledge and skills were required to manage National Nature Reserves. Neither contemporary agriculture (already obsessed with technical and economic ‘efficiency’ through intensification) nor forestry (focused since the end of World War I upon developing skills in tree-farming with exotic conifers, often in exposed upland sites) provided adequate models for very many of the new tasks of conservation.

New methods were required to manage less modified ecosystems for conservation, rather than production. These methods were progressively developed. Some involved the recovery of former rural management practices, such as cutting reed on wetlands, coppicing woodland or laying hedgerows. Some adapted farming systems, such as livestock grazing, but substituted a concern for altering grass swards (by resowing and fertilizing) to maximize production with a concern for maximizing plant or insect species diversity (through minimizing fertility and adjusting stock type and stocking density). After 200 years of animal breeding for production, conservationists rediscovered less improved breeds and ‘rare breeds’ of livestock; and even lowland fields and fens began to be grazed by Highland cattle, Hebridean sheep and Konik horses. Other techniques were more novel, including the use of mechanized cutters, manipulation of water levels or the selective use of herbicides (Green, 1981; Sutherland and Hill, 1995; Wallis DeVries et al, 2001). These skills were adapted and institutionalized into new and standardized regimes of management. They were shared within groups of often urban-based volunteers (for example, the British Trust for Conservation Volunteers) and became elements in formal college-taught courses.


_________________________________________________________________________________________

ECOLOGY CONSERVATION AND DISEQUILIBRIUM


New ideas of ‘non-equilibrium’ ecology call into question the tradition of intensive conservation management in places such as the UK that assumes that nature is (and should be) in equilibrium, and seeks to control ‘natural’ processes. The abundance and distribution of organisms, as well as the appearance of the landscape, are controlled by natural physical processes. One of the most important sources of disturbance in ecosystems is the working of physical processes in the landscape, particularly processes of erosion and deposition (Werrity et al, 1994). Some landscapes, such as sand dunes, beaches or river floodplains, are highly dynamic. Physical processes also drive environmental change elsewhere – for example, in woodlands affected by storms that cause trees to fall, or on mountain tops affected by freeze-thaw processes.

Standard approaches to sand dune management are based upon the control of ecological change and dune stabilization. This kind of intensive management is ineffective since it also leads to loss of early successional stages in dune ecosystems. You cannot ‘preserve’ such ecosystems by ‘managing’ them any more than you can by putting a fence around them and declaring them ‘protected’. Their biodiversity depends directly upon natural patterns of disturbance, driven by climate change. Indeed, their very existence depends upon such natural change, and in such environments disturbance must be seen as part of the ‘nature’ with which conservation is concerned. What you can do, of course, is to protect them, both from direct human exploitation (for example, quarrying of sand or shingle in the case of sand dunes) and from indirect human-induced change (for example, offshore dredging, or starvation of sediment by inappropriate coastal defence works). However, conservation then becomes not a matter of trying to dictate through management the exact form that nature takes, but of protecting processes of natural change from incompatible changes in economy and technology (Worster, 1994).

Ecologists have increasingly acknowledged the scientific challenge to old equilibrial ideas and have begun to consider the instabilities in landscapes, particularly the problem of disturbance, and different scales in space and time.

As the historian Donald Worster put it, ‘nature, we are told now, should be regarded as a landscape of patches of all sizes, textures, and colours, changing continually through time and space, responding to an unceasing barrage of perturbations’ (Worster, 1994). A ‘non-equilibrium paradigm’ in ecology emphasizes the openness of natural systems, and the need to understand them in the context of their surroundings, as well as the past events and disturbances that have affected them. Non-equilibrium ecology recognizes that the factors that are important in explaining how things change will depend upon the length of time and the area over which change is analysed (Steward et al, 1992). Ecology has undergone a profound shift from the notion that nature is a well-behaved, deterministic system towards a view in which equilibrium states are relatively unusual (Zoest, 1992).

Ideas about the fractal geometry of nature, and the idea that we should think of ecosystems as exhibiting the maths of chaos rather than the more comfortable dynamics of equilibrium, allow ecologists to begin to explore the ways in which different processes determine landscape pattern at different scales. Disturbances come in many shapes and sizes, from annual river floods or seasonal droughts to disease outbreaks. Ecologists suggest that in any given landscape, disturbances tend to occur at a characteristic scale, frequency and intensity that is determined by climate, weather, topography, geology and the species present. In river channels and floodplains, characteristic species and communities are maintained within different parts of the channel and the floodplain by processes of erosion and deposition, and by patterns of overbank flooding and groundwater recharge. If those processes are altered, ecological changes are likely to follow (Hughes, 1999; 2001).

Increasingly, during the last two centuries, there has been a human dimension to many ‘natural’ disturbances, and humans themselves have been major originators of disturbance (from local engineering activity to the release of carbon dioxide or ozone-depleting chemicals into the atmosphere). Ecologists can no longer work on the assumption that terrestrial ecosystems simply respond to climate changes and internal processes of competition. The scale and intensity of human activity is such that ecosystem change, driven by human action, can itself potentially drive climatic change. Ecology has to be able to shift scales in pursuit of explanation, reaching down to the molecular level and up to the global scale (May, 1989).

Conservationists should no longer conceive of nature in equilibrium, and therefore portray human-induced changes in those ecosystems as somehow ‘unnatural’. Nature is dynamic and highly variable. Its patterns at one particular place and time are contingent upon preceding events; its trajectory through time is open ended and does not tend towards an equilibrial point. Human actions are part of the web of influences on ecological change, not external equilibrium-disturbing impacts. The implication of this is that science cannot tell conservationists what nature ‘ought’ to be like, and it may not always even be able to describe what it used to be like, and how and why it has changed. Conservationists will very often need ecology, but their science gives them no privileged insight into the way nature should be. They will have to work that out the same way everyone else does, by thinking and talking about it.


_________________________________________

EQUILIBRIUM IN THE DRYLANDS


The idea that ecosystems have a ‘natural’ equilibrium state has also had significant impacts upon people, ecosystems and conservation in Africa. As in the case of conservation, pastoral policy has both needed and, in its turn, aided the growth of ecological science during the second half of the 20th century. In Africa, and in the US, from where the science mostly came, rangeland science drew upon wider advances in ecology, and provided clear evidence of ecology’s usefulness (see Chapter 2 in this book). Throughout the 20th century, most analyses of ecological change in the drylands of Africa were based upon this view of the ways in which ecosystems respond to human action – and upon rather sweeping assumptions about the ways in which people use land. From most perspectives (certainly those of pastoralists, although, by and large, nobody asked them), the impacts of equilibrium thinking have been negative.

The conventional scientific view of rangeland management and mis-management has been built around ideas of range condition class and carrying capacity. Scientific research has established that there is a general relationship between rainfall and biomass of herbivores, whether these are wild or domesticated (Coe et al, 1976). The conventional logic is that the environment is capable of supporting a certain fixed number of livestock (or biomass of herbivores) that for any given ecosystem can be calculated primarily as a function of rainfall. It can then be argued that at stocking levels lower than this carrying capacity, pasture resources are being underused, and that at higher stocking levels resources are being overused. In an unmanaged grazing system, such overgrazing would be likely to lead to ecological change that would reduce its productivity (for example, by causing the extinction of palatable species and the eventually loss of vegetation cover), leading to loss of condition in grazing animals and, eventually, to a reduction in their numbers.

Pastoralist overgrazing was widely seen by scientists and policy-makers in the 1970s as a principal cause of desertification. The Sahel drought of 1972–1974, and the longer period of reduced rainfall that began in 1968, led some observers to believe that climate was undergoing permanent change. A range of hypotheses suggested that rainfall reduction could result from overgrazing – for example, through the loss of green vegetation cover from the savanna and increased surface albedo, or increased levels of dust at high altitude, both of them leading to stable air masses and dry conditions (Adams, 2001). Rising human and livestock population densities were blamed for reductions in vegetation cover and enhanced soil erosion, and these, in turn, were blamed for producing ‘a new state of self-perpetuating drought’ (Sinclair and Fryxell, 1985, p992).

Rangeland scientists have applied exactly the same logic to human-managed grazing systems. Studies of pastoral people in Africa (and elsewhere) suggested that they lacked an understanding of the ecological impacts of high stock densities, and lacked institutions for controlling livestock numbers, or controlling who had access to grazing land. Ecological studies of pasture change seemed to confirm this. Superficial accounts of decision-making by stock-keepers (often made by Northern researchers arguing from ‘first principles’, rather than by anthropologists who might actually have discussed the question with local people, or by or indigenous people themselves) suggested that a ‘tragedy of the commons’ (the phrase coined by Hardin, 1968) was inevitable.

The concepts of overgrazing and carrying capacity condemned nomadic pastoralists because of their apparently feckless management of seemingly fragile rangelands (Swift, 1982; Horowitz and Little, 1987). In addition to the apparent scientific rationale for such strategies, governments also tended to distrust people who are mobile and difficult to locate, tax, educate and provide with services. Typical government pastoral policies had several components. They were aimed, for example, at adjusting grazing intensity to available grazing resources and, thus, at improving stock health and weight. This was done by reducing stock numbers through compulsory de-stocking, controlling stock distribution though fencing, and providing evenly distributed watering points and improvement of range condition through bush clearance, pasture reseeding and controlled burning. Projects also typically sought to persuade stock-keepers to sell their cattle commercially, and to promote breed improvement (by importing European or North American stock and breeding them) and disease control, all with the hope of instilling a proper regard for the weight and health of each animal. None of these strategies fitted with nomadic or semi-nomadic subsistence livestock production; therefore, government pastoral policy also emphasized fixed settlements, formal land tenure (freehold or leasehold) and capitalist production.

In conservation terms, this approach to pastoralism essentially achieved two things, neither of them helpful. Firstly, it failed to recognize, or allow for, the historical tolerance of pastoralists for wildlife (Homewood and Rodgers, 1991; Homewood and Brockington, 1999). In doing so, it forced a conceptual and practical separation of areas managed for wildlife – protected areas (PAs) – and those managed for people and ‘development’. It defined conservation as something done in spite of, against the interests of, and in the face of the opposition of pastoral people. Wherever pastoral management became more intensive (for example, where ranching systems were adopted), wildlife became increasingly unwelcome, a reservoir of disease (rinderpest, foot and mouth, bovine pleuropneumonia and sleeping sickness). Until the rise of game farming for safari hunting in southern Africa from the 1980s, and the growth of game-watching safari tourism, livestock grazing and wildlife were seen as mutually inimical activities.

The second result of this view of pastoralists as degrading the environment was the rigorous exclusion of pastoral people from protected areas: if nature ought to be in equilibrium, and humans and their livestock disrupted that equilibrium, then ‘natural’ areas had to be rid of people and their animals. And they were: most of the famous savanna national parks and reserves in eastern Africa were established on former pastoralist land (admittedly, sometimes on land whose users had been decimated by warfare and famine following the introduction of rinderpest and various other disasters; see Waller, 1988; Anderson and Johnson, 1988). In many parks (for example, at Amboseli National Park and Maasai Mara Game Reserve in Kenya; in the Serengeti National Park and Ngorogoro Conservation Area, Arusha National Park and the Mkomazi Game Reserve in Tanzania), people were evicted, or restricted in their use of land and resources. Access has been, in some instances, the subject of long-running and bitter dispute (Lindsay, 1987; Homewood and Rodgers, 1991; Brockington and Homewood, 1996; Neumann, 1998; Brockington 2002). This notion that people can and should be excluded from protected areas because they are places for ‘wild’ nature reflects the broader Western enthusiasm for wilderness (see Chapter 2). The portrayal of African savannas as ‘wilderness’, untouched, until recently, by human hand, is, of course, fundamentally flawed, as it is elsewhere – for example, Australia (see Chapters 3 and 4)

Researchers have increasingly expressed reservations about the universal applicability of the concept of overgrazing and with the unreflective links drawn between it and desertification (Sandford, 1983; Horowitz and Little, 1987; Mace, 1991). It has been argued that overstocking or overgrazing are rarely defined, and that judgements about carrying capacity are subjective, although that subjectivity is rarely admitted (Hogg, 1983; Homewood and Rodgers, 1984; 1987). They have become both entrenched and self-reinforcing.

It is now recognized that there are wide gaps between pastoral policy prescriptions and the ways in which pastoral people actually manage their herds and rangelands. Pastoral development planning tends to focus upon commercial cattle production for slaughter for the production of meat and hides, whereas indigenous production systems tend to emphasize the production of products from live animals (milk or blood). Commercial production systems also typically focus upon a single species (usually cattle of an improved variety), whereas indigenous production systems tend to mix different kinds of livestock in their herds (cattle and camels and goats, for example, among the Turkana in northern Kenya; Coughenour et al, 1985). Moreover, poorer pastoral households will hold different a range of stock from wealthy ones. Mixed flocks and herds allow flexible use of land, water and vegetation resources in space and time. Unlike commercial ranching systems, indigenous pastoral ecosystems seem well adapted to exploit the spatial and temporal variability in biological production. Such systems offer a relatively low output compared to modern capitalist systems, such as ranching. However, they are remarkably robust in terms of providing a predictable, if limited, livelihood. Standardized assumptions about herd management, and formulaic prescriptions of carrying capacity are a poor guide to what happens on the ground.


________________________________________________

DISEQUILIBRIUM AND DRYLAND ENVIRONMENTS


Despite massive research and a multitude of publications on the subject of desertification, which began with the Sahel drought of the 1970s and has been maintained in the face of persistent low rainfall in Africa ever since, it has slowly come to be recognized that the data necessary to assess ‘long-term degradation’ of vegetation or desertification, in most cases, simply does not exist (Warren, 1996; Swift, 1996; Adams, 2001). While it is clear that dryland rainfall in Africa varies from year to year (and in the timing and consistency of rainfall within years), this is not now blamed on farmers and pastoralists. Today, explanations emphasize the larger-scale links to global ocean–atmosphere circulation, particularly sea surface temperatures in the southern Atlantic and Indian oceans (Hulme, 1996; 2001).

Conventional thinking about carrying capacity and overgrazing began to be challenged during the 1980s and 1990s by so-called ‘new range ecology’ (Behnke and Scoones, 1991). New ideas hold that pastoral strategies are designed to track environmental variation (taking advantage of wet years,and coping with dry ones), rather than being conservative (seeking a steady-state equilibrial output). This awareness of the non-equilibrial nature of savanna ecosystem dynamics reflects a wider understanding of the importance of non-linear processes in ecology, as a whole (see, for example, Botkin, 1990; Pahl-Wostl, 1995). Much of what appeared to be perversity or conservatism on the part of pastoralists is revealed to be highly adaptive (Behnke and Scoones, 1991; Behnke et al, 1993).

The productivity of semi-arid rangelands varies a great deal both seasonally and between years. The primary cause of this variation is rainfall, which is now acknowledged to be highly variable in space and time in sub-Saharan Africa, particularly in drier rangelands. Here, ecosystems exhibit non-equilibrial behaviour, and ecosystem state and productivity are largely driven externally. The varied influences of fire, soil fertility and groundwater add to the complexity of rangeland productivity and its capacity to support grazing at particular places and times. There is no automatic ecological succession under grazing pressure towards an overgrazed state; instead, there are complex patterns of ecological change in response to exogenous conditions (especially rainfall) and stock numbers and management. Such ecological changes can take many forms, not all of them serious, and they can proceed by diverse routes, some of which can be reversed more easily than others, and some of which are more sensitive to particular management than others. Arguably, there are no ‘naturally’ stable points in semi-arid ecosystems that can usefully be taken to define an ‘equilibrial’ state.

Studies of the responses of vegetation to different stocking levels, or of livestock numbers, tend to take no account of seasonal or annual variations in fodder availability, and tend to be built upon estimates of regional stocking rates. Such estimates are notoriously unreliable because livestock are difficult and expensive to count, particularly if their owners do not want you to do so. Studies identifying overgrazing also tend to concentrate on absolute numbers of livestock and not on densities, rarely consider spatial mobility, and fail to take account of spatial and temporal variations. Conventional ideas about the overstocking of rangelands also typically fail to take account of the ways in which indigenous pastoralists understand the environment and adapt to it – particularly the skill with which they move stock around in response to seasonal environmental change in drier and wetter years, and the importance of institutions for the exchange and recovery of stock through kinship networks. Indigenous pastoralists can manage herds, and grazing land, in detailed, complex and often effective ways.

The attempt to define a single carrying capacity for an ecosystem with great annual variation in primary productivity is problematic (Homewood and Rodgers, 1987). The attempt to do so implies that the ecosystem has an optimal equilibrium state. If that equilibrium is illusory (because of the variability and resilience of the ecosystem), the concept of carrying capacity can only be relevant as a social or economic, rather than an ecological, concept – a judgement about the density of animals and plants that allows managers to get what they want out of the ecosystem (Homewood and Rodgers, 1987). The goals of a subsistence pastoralist, a rancher and a conservationist are likely to be very different. The pastoralist might wish to maintain herd size as capital and exchange value, as well as yields of milk and blood. The rancher needs to ensure profitable returns of capital through disease-free meat off-take. The conservationist seeks to maintain the ‘naturalness’ of the ecosystem and, like the rancher, probably wishes to fix the changing ecosystem in what is assumed to be its ‘natural’ state.

It may therefore be perfectly rational for the pastoralist to run a larger biomass of livestock than the rancher would, or than the conservationist would wish to do. Many African systems do, indeed, have a subsistence stocking rate that is higher than commercial ranchers would adopt, giving low rates of production per animal but high output per unit area (Homewood and Rodgers, 1987). This is not a mistake; it reflects people managing their assets in response to a different set of needs and different kinds of social arrangements and market signals.

It is now widely accepted that pastoral ecosystems should not be thought of as having a specific carrying capacity, equating to the density of livestock that can be supported at equilibrium, particularly if that density has been calculated for a commercial meat extraction system. Actual stocking levels can exceed such a standardized carrying capacity in a number of years successively (Behnke and Scoones, 1991). The critical point is that there is a constantly changing balance of grazing pressure and range resources. In wetter years, stock numbers rise (and animal condition and disease status improves). In dry years, stock lose condition and health. Severe drought years first reduce the condition of stock and then (through disease, death and destitution-forced sales) reduce stock numbers. When good rains follow, they allow pastures to recover, resulting in a lagged recovery of herd numbers as pastoralists track environmental conditions. Livestock numbers, like the ecosystem more generally, boom and bust with the rainfall.

To survive without degrading the environment, herd managers not only need their extensive knowledge of environmental conditions and opportunities in different areas open to them, but require access to those areas. Prevention of access because of government schemes for irrigation of large-scale agriculture (Hogg, 1983; Lane, 1992), or because of the establishment of protected areas (Brockington and Homewood, 1996; Homewood and Brockington, 1999; Brockington, 2002), can be a disaster.

Nature in the dry grasslands of Africa is not in equilibrium at all. Strategies to support environmental and social sustainability need to foster indigenous capacity in order to track rainfall and maintain social and economic networks, rather than demand a shift to a static, equilibrial capitalist form of production. Conservation need not automatically sign up to a policy of excluding people and their livestock. There is evidence that livestock and wildlife can run together without disaster at a wide range of densities; where they are incompatible, it is often livestock that suffer because of their susceptibility to disease (Homewood and Rodgers, 1991). Even in protected areas where pastoralist evictions are recent (for example, the Mkomazi Game Reserve in northern Tanzania, cleared in 1988), evidence of environmental degradation due to human occupation can be inconclusive or inadequate (Homewood and Brockington, 1999; Brockington, 2002)

Conservation planning in pastoral areas needs to ask more careful questions about people’s role in the ways in which the environment is changing. Firstly, the long historical role of people in savanna ecosystems needs to be acknowledged, and any discussion of naturalness must be based upon clear historical and palaeo-environmental research. Secondly, arguments about the incompatibility of human occupation and biodiversity need to be based upon clear and specific research, and not upon general assumptions founded on unproved hypotheses about the equilibrial state of ecosystems and the risk of ‘overgrazing’. Thirdly, conservation visions need to take specific account of the ideas that local residents have about nature – what is the area like, how is it changing, and which aspects of that change are acceptable and which not? Fourthly, in drylands, as everywhere else, conservation needs to learn to move forward in collaboration with local land users, instead of trying to bulldoze them aside.


________________________________________________

NATURALNESS AND THE CONTROL OF NATURE



The idea that nature can be thought of as a set of ecosystems that tend to exist in equilibrium has led to an intrusive, and sometimes destructive, approach to conservation and to thinking about human use and degradation of natural resources. This seems to be so in contexts as widely divergent as the petite nature reserves of the UK and the expanses of African savannas. Of course, in many ways, these environments are not far apart at all; they are linked by the developing discipline of ecology and the colonial networks of science and ideology (see Chapters 2 and 7 in this book). Both of these reflect the scientific

Image

rationalization of nature that is characteristic of 20th-century colonial ideas (see Chapter 3). Nature conservation can be seen as a social practice that regulates (or seeks to regulate) relations between humans and non-human nature. It operates both within certain terrains or spaces (such as protected areas) and through a generalized moral discourse. That discourse often revolves around, and is developed through, specific conserved (or ‘threatened’) spaces.

The history of conservation practice reveals two contrasting dimensions (see Table 10.1). The first is what I would call ‘the conservation of wildness’. This arises from a concern for wild nature, naturalness and unaltered ‘non-human’ nature. Robert Elliot (1997) points out in Faking Nature the importance of the view that ‘wild nature’ has intrinsic value. This wildness of nature comprises the basis for the cultural values of nature that have come to dominate conservation in the industrialized world. It explains one fundamental reason why people in countries such as the UK value nature (Adams, 1996). [7] The historical dimensions of this enthusiasm for notions of ‘the wild’ are discussed in Chapter 2 of this book

The second dimension of conservation is very different, and I have called it ‘conservation as control’ (see Table 10.1). This is conservation as the technical practice of the control of nature. It has become the characteristic approach to conservation in the UK and in places that have adopted British conservation ideas. The science of ecology, the techniques of habitat management and the bureaucratic/planning procedures of nature reserve management all represented an attempt to define and control the forms that non-human nature took (Adams, 1997). Reserves and other defined terrain were designated because of the ‘wildness’or ‘naturalness’of nature;but once established,they were mostly closely managed in order to keep nature within fixed bounds. Indeed, ecological research told conservation planners what nature ought to look like. Nature reserves were places where non-human nature could be maintained as it ought to be – its naturalness preserved and sometimes recreated (for example, this occurred when myxamatosis wiped out rabbits and chalk grasslands became hawthorn scrub, or when shallow water bodies became wet woodland habitats).

The tight management regimes of British nature reserves are one obvious context for this tradition of conservation as control, but the principle is more widely applicable. In the language of Birch (1990), any attempt to bound and protect ‘nature’ effectively put wildness in prison. He suggests that wilderness preservation (the US’s defining contribution to global conservation; Henderson, 1992), is ‘another stanza in the same old imperialist song of Western civilization’ (Henderson, 1992, p4). His argument is an interesting one. He suggests that by the very act of designating ‘wilderness’ reserves for wild nature, the ‘otherness’ of wild land is itself locked up. Such reservation limits what humans can do to specified pieces of nature, and keeps people who might destroy wildness out; but it also allows humanity to contain and control the wild completely. Such ‘wilderness’ exists at the whim of legislators and government policy. Furthermore, such wilderness reservations can be (and are) managed in various ways, even if that management is disguised to hide it from human visitors’ eyes. Thus, the wildness of nature is subjugated to a specified regime of human planning, bringing the outcomes of natural processes within a range acceptable to society. Birch comments: ‘the imperium [the supreme or imperial power of Western civilization] has the power to manage, invade, declassify, abolish, de-sanctify the legal wildland entities it has created, and the creation of such entities on its terms does little to diminish this power’ (Birch, 1990, p22).

The tension between the values attached to ‘wild’ nature and the need to control that wildness is much more broadly relevant than simply wildlife conservation. Perhaps the clearest example lies in the way river floods are understood and managed. For centuries, river management has tended to follow the ‘rational use’ element within conservation, informed by the need to control floods and bring the benefits of water (irrigation, water meadows, water supply and, latterly, hydroelectric power) to society.
This has demanded control of rivers and their waters: the dominant metaphors of river engineering are damming, harnessing, taming the mighty river, or bringing the desert to bloom. These ideologies were central to the American West as Donald Worster’s Rivers of Empire (1985) and Mark Reisner’s Cadillac Desert (1986) make clear, just as they were to imperial dreams in the Sahara (see Chapter 2) and colonial and post-colonial engineers who dammed Africa’s major rivers (the Nile, Zambezi, Volta and Niger; Adams, 1992). Dams personified the ‘can-do’ of engineering, the capacity to out-think and control nature, to tame the wild. They create a macho world of concrete, steel and human endeavour.

Of course, in the UK things have been less butch; but the family resemblance to colonial ideologies of controlling nature is clear. One might consider the urge for developing the Scottish hydropower schemes of the 1930s (Sheail, 1981), the creation of Lake Efyrnwy and the flooding of the Elan Valley during the late 19th century to supply Birmingham with water, or the development of hydropower in north Wales (Gruffudd, 1990). The spirit of control is beautifully captured by the character of ‘Mr Galvanic’, fictional employee of the British Electricity Authority in the Clough Williams-Ellises’ book Headlong Down the Years: ‘If I had my way, this disgusting water would soon know its place! The place for water is behind dams and in pipes – all under control’ (Gruffudd, 1990, p165, quoting Amabel and Clough Williams-Ellis, 1951)

Conservationists have frequently been opposed to dam construction, along with the wider environmental movement. One could think of the classic dispute over a dam in the Hetch Hetchy Valley in the US Yosemite National Park between the romantic preservationist John Muir and the gritty utilitarian conservationist Gifford Pinchot; Edward Abbey’s book The Monkey Wrench Gang (1975), whose heroes are obsessed with the destruction of the Glen Canyon Dam on the Colorado River; or the work of Dan Brouwer and the Sierra Club (Brouwer was quoted as saying: ‘I hate all dams, large and small’; Finkhouse and Crawford, 1991). Outside the US, the protests of local people and Indian environmentalists against the Sardar Sarovar Dam on the Narmada River comprise one example of the strength and diversity of environmentalist opposition to large dams (Adams, 2001).
Last edited by NonZeroSum on Fri May 19, 2017 3:55 am, edited 1 time in total.
Unofficial librarian of vegan and socialist movement media.
PhiloVegan Wiki: https://tinyurl.com/y7jc6kh6
Vegan Video Library: https://tinyurl.com/yb3udm8x
Ishkah YouTube: https://youtube.com/Ishkah
User avatar
NonZeroSum
Master of the Forum
Posts: 1159
Joined: Fri Feb 10, 2017 6:30 am
Diet: Vegan
Location: North Wales, UK

Re: When nature won’t stay still: Conservation, equilibrium and control by William M Adams

Post by NonZeroSum »

____________________________________

RESTORING NATURE



The attraction of dams to their builders, and the issue behind the specific fears of their opponents, is the question of control over ‘wild’ nature. In the UK, flood control and the ‘reclamation’ of land liable to flood for urban development and agriculture have a long history. There is a dominant paradigm of ‘flood control’ that involves the defence of society and its capital and infrastructure against the incursions of wild nature. Institutionally, it has been inspired by the power of particular events, such as the great East Anglian floods of the 1950s, although the engineering is much older and the urge is ancient. Flood control (under Internal Drainage Boards and the Water Authorities, now the Environment Agency) has almost exclusively involved ‘hard-engineering’ solutions to the problems of flooding: changing the course, cross-section and regime of rivers with concrete banks, flood channels and culverts, as well as dams and barrages. The impact on riparian and aquatic ecosystems, wildlife and landscape has been vast and negative. During the 20th century, British rivers have become steadily less natural and less diverse.

Recently, there have been shifts in the control paradigm that has dominated river management (RSPB, 1994). Successive pieces of legislation have strengthened the requirements on river managers to have regard for conservation. This is all part of a wider shift towards ‘soft engineering’, rooted, for example, in the landscape design ideas of Ian McHarg’s Design with Nature (1969).

One major fruit of the new river management paradigm is the growing interest in river restoration (Boon et al, 1992; Brookes and Shields, 1996). A great deal of energy in conservation and environmental planning in industrialized countries is now going into ecological restoration (Jordan et al, 1987a; Perrow and Davy, 2002). It is a new science, but has its own learned society and academic journal (Restoration Ecology).8 The idea of ecological restoration nicely captures the tension between conservation’s concern for the naturalness of nature and its confidence in its ability to predict, control and create nature.

River restoration typically involves replacing relatively small physical and biological elements of floodplains and channels. Most work is in low-energy floodplains, where created or recreated physical features tend to stay where they are put. The prime example of such work in the UK is probably the work of the River Restoration Project. Of their restoration work on the small lowland River Cole, one journalist remarked that ‘engineers spent 900 years taming the River Cole in Oxfordshire by straightening it and deepening its bed to provide power for mills and to avoid floods – and then decided it was a mistake. During the past two years they have spent UK£150,000 reversing the process and recreating the river as it must have looked in the 16th century by putting the kinks back in’ (Brown, 1997, p11).

Is restoration a science? Not exactly. Turner (1987) argues that it is neither a science nor a technology, for its goal is not product but process: ‘one could say that the biological machine the restorer produces has no function but its own ordered reproduction’ (Turner, 1987, p48). Turner argues that restoration is, in fact, an art: ‘The attempt to reproduce accurately the functions of nature forces the artist not only to increasingly close observation, but beyond, to increasingly stringent experimental tests of ideas. This labour, so understood, is not merely analytical, but creative, and its natural reward is beauty’ (Turner, 1987, p50).

Science is, however, central to the practice of restoration, and restoration is central to the science of ecology: ‘the business of restoration and management [is] not just the acid test of its ideas, but [is] the very source of many of them as well’ (Jordan and Packard, 1989, p26). The key to restoration is understanding the assembly rules by which species accumulate into assemblages (Keddy, 1999). With an inanimate object such as a clock, an ability to assemble it from pieces and adjust it properly suggests that ‘perhaps we can claim to understand it’ (Jordan et al, 1987b, p16). The restored ecosystem is a copy, of course. An analogy might be the work of a vintage car repairer. Nature is a machine, and if the vintage parts are reassembled, or modern facsimiles made, it will run much as before, although adjustments may have been made so that it can use modern petrol or meet safety standards. To all but the most hardened purist, a few modern components are hardly worth objecting to in the context of the wider achievements of the project.

The capacity of ecologists to predict and control nature is central to the restoration project: ‘The essential idea is control – the ability to restore quickly but to restore at will, controlling speed, decelerating change, as well as accelerating it, reversing it, altering its course, steering it, even preventing it entirely (which, of course, is actually a frequent objective of the ecological manager)’ (Jordan et al, 1987b, p17). Restoration is, therefore, at one level, restoration of naturalness. At another, however, it is the reverse, since the whole science of restoration is based upon the ability to predict outcomes and compare them to some template. Keddy stresses the importance of ecological indicators in restoration projects, emphasizing ‘the ability to evaluate whether manipulation has produced the desired change’ (Keddy, 1999, p718).

However, in ecological restoration, a distinction can be drawn between restoring form and restoring form-creating processes – for example, between replanting a wood and simply allowing woodland to develop by leaving a patch of grassland alone. Living systems self-repair, and restoration may involve ‘bringing in certain key “ingredients”, then letting nature take its course in shaping the result’ (Jordan et al, 1987b, p16). In floodplains, this involves more than putting pieces of habitat ‘back’; it entails linking them hydrologically, and in terms of sediment flux and geochemistry, with each other and the river channel and allowing ecosystems to evolve (Hughes, 2001). Johan van Zoest (1992) urges the ‘management of processes rather than patterns’ in sand dunes. He advocates the relaxation of control over the processes active in dunes, a process he calls ‘gambling with nature’. He suggests that conservationists should think of managing nature as a game, not as tending a machine. Rather than trying to control nature, management is best done by thinking like a player in a game. Conservation should not manipulate populations and communities in order to achieve defined outcomes, but should expect complex and unexpected effects of human actions. Managers therefore should willingly play a game with nature, even if they have (or think they have) deep scientific understanding of the ecological rules of play and the role of chance processes.


_________________________________________________

RESTORATION AND THE CONTROL OF NATURE



Most ecological restoration, however, is less open spirited than this. Particularly in ecosystems with the capacity to cause damage to human interests (for example, rivers that flood), those proposing restoration must feel confident of being able to predict the outcome of the restoration process, or at least of specifying the range of conditions within which it will lie. Either way, restoration, in practice, demands prediction and the control of outcomes, and restoration projects in environments such as rivers will, in practice, usually be small in scale and limited in imagination. Restoration is almost always, therefore, creating naturalness within fixed bounds. How are these bounds fixed? Remarkably, there is increasing capacity to do without physical boundaries for nature.

Restoration work within river channels has made use of the last 20 years of fluvial geomorphology and the understanding it offers of how rivers behave. However, studies of river geomorphology are shifting. The dominant approach since the 1950s has been largely empirical, involving the statistical analysis of the physical shape of river channels, such as channel width and depth and meander wavelength, and the measurement of surrogates for the variables that control them (particularly river discharge). This approach implied that river channels were equilibrial at the scale of the reach. However, numerical generalizations no longer satisfy river scientists. Research is increasingly moving to a smaller scale, and to the intensive measurement of the ways in which channels respond to changes in discharge, sediment supply and other factors in small reaches of rivers over short time periods (Lane and Richards, 1997). Studies of real rivers are now being combined with studies of virtual rivers through laboratory experimentation and computer modelling. It turns out that (as with ecosystems) short-term, small-scale events have significance at a larger scale: rivers may behave as non-linear systems. The key to understanding them is to see them as dynamic systems; research must integrate work within and outside of nature, ’ in the field, the flume and the computer’ (Lane and Richards, 1997, p258).

New technologies of surveillance using micro-chip technology yield vast volumes of data about river behaviour. Computer models allow such data to be run through models of river behaviour. Nature can be described with an intensity and level of detail never previously known, and nature’s agency – its capacity to act – is predicted with a precision never previously known. As uncertainty falls, management confidence rises. This is essentially why river managers have been willing to consider ecological restoration. The science behind them allows them to move safely away from their traditional (and highly expensive) approach of confining rivers within artificial channels and behind barrages in order to ‘control’ floods. In ‘restoring’ the river, river managers can cut nature more slack because they think that they know what will happen when they take the concrete and the dams away.

Greater knowledge of rivers, therefore, creates more confident management. Managers no longer fear the power of the ‘natural’ river – they do not need to control it because they understand it. The conservation turn of river management represents a greater openness to the ‘natural’ attributes of rivers. Restoration meets the new conservation objectives. However, control is not lost: it is simply that physical restraint is exchanged for knowledge-based ability in order to predict how nature will work.
In this sense, restoration (‘the ultimate test for ecology’) is a logical development of the rationalizing project of control. As conservation tries to move away from a concern for particular ‘equilibrial’ forms of ecosystems, by concentrating on the regimes of processes that give rise to those forms, we are, perhaps, not escaping the ideology of control as completely as we might like to believe. Our scientific and technical skills allow us to intensify our attempts to control nature under the guise of conservation. The abandonment of old equilibrial thinking may, therefore, not usher in a new era of egalitarian engagement between people and non-human nature, but a new regime of control. We may no longer need to intervene in the detailed way in which we did in conservation management; in a sense, science and technology, and new theories of ecosystem behaviour, allow us to achieve more control than ever before. We have control not by controlling nature’s every move, but, more cost effectively, by thinking nature’s thoughts.


___________________________________

CONCLUSIONS


This chapter has tried to argue that our beliefs in the innate equilibrial behaviour of nature have a number of significant implications for the way in which we approach the management or conservation of nature. A number of these might well make us uncomfortable. Formal policies for land management in the pastoral drylands of Africa have not only been unsuccessful but also, in many instances, unhelpful or even harmful for pastoralists. Conservationists have shared the standardized ecological understanding of savanna dynamics and have, perhaps, been slower than livestock planners to admit that the science needs a very thorough second look, and that they need to rethink their ideas about what is ‘natural’ and what is ‘sustainable’.
In the UK, these same ecological themes have resulted in a wonderfully intricate practice of conservation management. Using these skills, conservation has maintained astonishing proportions of Britain’s rather impoverished fauna and flora on a tiny proportion of the land surface – small isolated islands of semi-natural habitat marooned in a sea of chemical agriculture, roads and houses. This is a wonderful achievement; but this approach to conservation leaves nature trussed up, delivered with something like the same factory-like precision as the agricultural crops and industrial products that have so widely supplanted it. Even in conservation, the obsession has been to control nature, to ensure that its biodiversity is sustained, to provide it with special places – but, at the same time, to keep its wildness under control.

Ideas about ecological restoration challenge established ideas about conservation, and ideas about the restoration of natural processes, rather than simply natural features, challenge them further. These initiatives are exciting (and are discussed further in Chapter 11); but even in this enthusiasm for restoration, the human need for control rears its head. I have suggested that where (as in the case of rivers) we have been willing to take the concrete out and allow natural features back in, we seem to need to retain control, even if it is only exercised through our computer models.

There are, therefore, two challenges that lend themselves to a form of conservation based upon the idea that nature is non-equilibrial. The first starts from the premise of business as usual, where conservation does, and should, involve a large measure of human agency and control. The question is simple: who should decide about the form that nature takes? This is relevant in the UK (where river planners, conservation planners and local residents might have very different views about the desirability of letting a river flood). It is even more relevant in places such as Africa, where conservationists (and development planners) still tend to come into rural communities, from capital cities and foreign consultancies, donor organizations and non-governmental organizations (NGOs), with their agendas pre-formed. As Chapters 4, 5 and 6 all show, conservation is still not a very inclusive discourse. Conservation can make some heavy demands on people who live in biodiverse places, demands that they sometimes find inexplicable and unfair. Who should get to forge conservation policy? How should local needs and wider conservation interests be balanced? How can locally diverse ideas of nature be reconciled with national and global priorities for conservation? These are widely recognized issues.

The second challenge for conservation that arises from recognizing non-equilibrial ecology relates to a point made in several places in this book. It concerns the idea that nature is, by definition, wild: that which is unknown, uncontrolled. Can we imagine a conservation that recognizes and allows nature to be wild? Or is conservation, in Thomas Birch’s words (1990, p8) ‘just another move in the imperial resource allocation game? [9]


NOTES

1 National Nature Reserves (NNRs) and Sites of Special Scientific Interest (SSSIs) are statutory government conservation designations by English Nature. They originated under the Nature Conservancy, established in 1949 (Adams, 1996).
2 I still use the photographs I took of these places in lectures, although the stories I tell about them have changed over time.
3 See www.davidaxford.free-online.co.uk/torreycn.htm, 30 July 2001. 4 Rachel Carson (1963) Silent Spring.
5 Marsh expresses this gendered discourse clearly: ‘The ravages committed by man subvert the relations and destroy the balance which nature had established between her organized and her inorganic creations’ (Marsh, 1864, p42).
6 I am grateful to John Rodwell for this observation.
7 Note that this is the case regardless of the fact that UK nature is substantially human made (‘semi-natural’, to use Arthur Tansley’s phrase). Most targets of conservation action are hybrids of human agency and non-human agency (for example, heathlands, chalk grasslands, ancient woodlands). Only a few ‘natural formations’ do not bear in their formation the obvious imprint of deliberate human agency (exceptions include some Scottish peat bogs and alpine plant communities, a few cliff forest understorey fragments or other communities on remote cliffs, and the vegetation of ephemeral environments, such as river banks and islands, or salt marshes or sand dunes).
8 See www.blackwell-science.com.
9 I would like to thank Martin Mulligan, Dan Brockington and Francine Hughes for their comments on this chapter.


REFERENCES

Abbey, E (1975) The Monkey Wrench Gang. J B Lippincott, New York
Adams, W M (1992) Wasting the Rain: rivers, people and planning in Africa. Minnesota University Press, Minneapolis, Minnesota
Adams, W M (1996) Future Nature: a vision for conservation. Earthscan, London Adams, W M (1997) ‘Rationalization and conservation: ecology and the management
of nature in the United Kingdom’, Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers NS, vol 22, pp277–291
Adams, W M (2001) Green Development: Environment and Sustainability in the Third World, second edition. Routledge, London
Allen, D E (1976) The Naturalist in Britain. Penguin, Harmondsworth, UK
Anderson, D M and Johnson, D H (1988) ‘Ecology and society in north-east African history’ in D Johnson and D M Anderson (eds) The Ecology of Survival: case studies from North-East African history. Lester Crook, London, pp1–26
Behnke, R H and Scoones, I (1991) Rethinking Range Ecology: implications for range management in Africa. ODI/IIED, London
Behnke, R H Jr, Scoones, I and Kerven, C (1993) Range Ecology at Disequilibrium: new models of natural variability and pastoral adaptation in African savannas. Overseas Development Institute, London
Birch, T H (1990) ‘The incarceration of wildness: wilderness areas as prisons’, Environmental Ethics, vol 12(1), pp3–26
Boon, P J, Calow, P and Petts, G E (eds) (1992) River Conservation and Management, Wiley, Chichester
Botkin, D B (1990) Discordant Harmonies: a new ecology for the twenty-first century. Oxford University Press, New York
Brockington, D (2002) Fortress Conservation: the preservation of the Mkomazi Game Reserve. James Currey, Oxford
Brockington, D and Homewood, K (1996) ‘Wildlife, pastoralists and science: debates concerning Mkomazi Game Reserve, Tanzania’ in M Leach and R Mearns (eds) The Lie of the Land. James Currey, Oxford, pp91–104
Brookes, A and Shields, F (eds) (1996) River Channel Restoration: guiding principles for sustainable projects. John Wiley and Sons Ltd, Chichester
Brown, P (1997) ‘Tailored river gets back its bends’, Guardian, Friday, 17 September 1997, p11
Carson, R (1963) Silent Spring, Hamilton, London
Clements, F E (1905) Research Methods in Ecology. University Publishing Company, Lincoln, Nebraska
Clements, F E (1916) Plant Succession: an analysis of the development of vegetation. Carnegie Institute, Washington, D C, Publication 290
Coe, M J, Cummings, D H and Phillipson, J (1976) ‘Biomass and production of large African herbivores in relation to rainfall and primary production’, Oecologia, vol 22, pp341–354
Coughenour, M B, Ellis, J E, Swift, D M, Coppock, D L, Galvin, K, McCabe, J T and Hart, T C (1985) ‘Energy extraction and use in a nomadic pastoral ecosystem’, Nature, vol 230, pp619–625
Duffey, E (1970) ‘The management of Woodwalton Fen: a multidisciplinary approach’ in E Duffey and A S Watt (eds) The Scientific Management of Animal and Plant Communities for Conservation. Blackwell, Oxford, pp581–597
Duffey , E and Watt, A S (eds) (1970) The Scientific Management of Animal and Plant Communities for Conservation. Blackwell, Oxford
Elliot, R (1997) Faking Nature: the ethics of environmental restoration. Routledge, London Finkhouse, J and Crawford, M (eds) (1991) A River Too Far: the past and future of the Arid
West. University of Nevada Press, Reno
Gleason, H A (1926) ‘The individualistic concept of the plant association’, Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club, vol 53, pp7–26
Green, B (1981) Countryside Conservation. Allen and Unwin, London
Griffiths, T (1996) Hunters and Collectors: The Antiquarian Imagination in Australia. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Grove, R H (1992) ‘Origins of western environmentalism’, Scientific American, vol 267, pp42–47
Grove, R H (1995) Green Imperialism: colonial expansion, tropical island Edens and the origins of environmentalism, 1600–1800. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Gruffudd, P (1990) ‘Uncivil engineering: nature, nationalism and hydro-electrics in north Wales’ in D Cosgrove and G Petts (eds) Water, Engineering and Landscape: water control and landscape transformation in the modern period. Belhaven Press, London, pp159–173
Hardin, G (1968) ‘The tragedy of the commons’, Science, vol 1628, pp1243–1248 Henderson, N (1992) ‘Wilderness and the nature conservation ideal: Britain, Canada
and the United States contrasted’, Ambio, vol 21, pp394–399
Hill, M O (1979) TWINSPAN – a FORTRAN Program for Arranging Multivariate Data in an Ordered Two–Way Table by Classification of the Individuals and Attributes. Cornell University, Ithaca, New York
Hogg, R (1983) ‘Irrigation agriculture and pastoral development: a lesson from Kenya’, Development and Change, vol 14, pp577–591
Homewood, K and Brockington, D (1999) ‘Biodiversity, conservation and development in Mkomazi Game Reserve, Tanzania’, Global Ecology and Biodiversity, vol 8, pp301–313
Homewood, K and Rodgers, W A (1984) ‘Pastoralism and conservation’, Human Ecology, vol 12, pp431–441
Homewood, K and Rodgers, W A (1987) ‘Pastoralism, conservation and the overgrazing controversy’, in D M Anderson and R H Grove (eds) Conservation in Africa: people, policies and practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp111–128
Homewood, K and Rodgers, W A (1991) Masailand Ecology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Horowitz, M M and Little, P D (1987) ‘African pastoralism and poverty: some implications for drought and famine’ in M Glantz (ed) Drought and Hunger in Africa: denying famine a future. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp59–82
Hughes, F M R (1999) ‘Floodplain biogeomorphology’, Progress in Physical Geography, vol 21, pp501–529
Hughes, F M R (2001) ‘Floodplains’ in A Warren and J R French (eds) Habitat Conservation: managing the physical environment. J Wiley and Sons, Chichester, pp103–121
Hulme, M (1996) Climate change within the period of meteorological records’ in W M Adams, A S Goudie and A R Orme (eds) (1996) The Physical Geography of Africa. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp88–102
Hulme, M (2001) ‘Climatic perspectives on Sahelian desiccation: 1973–1998’, Global Environmental Change, vol 11, pp19–29
Huston, M A (1994) Biological Diversity: the coexistence of species on changing landscapes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Jordan, W R III and Packard, S (1989) ‘Just a few oddball species: restoration practice and ecological theory’ in G P Buckely (ed) Biological Habitat Reconstruction. Belhaven Press, London, pp18–28
Jordan, W R III, Gilpin, M E and Aber, J D (eds) (1987a) Restoration Ecology: A Synthetic Approach to Ecological Research, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Jordan, W R III, Gilpin, M E and Aber, J D (1987b) ‘Restoration ecology: restoration as a technique for basic research’ in W R Jordan III, M E Gilpin and J D Aber (eds) Restoration Ecology: A Synthetic Approach to Ecological Research. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp3–21
Keddy, P (1999) ‘Wetland restoration: the potential for assembly rules in the service of conservation’, Wetlands, vol 19, pp716–732
Lane, C (1992) ‘The Barabaig Pastoralists of Tanzania: sustainable land use in jeopardy’ in D Ghai and J M Vivian (eds) Grassroots Environmental Action: people’s participation in sustainable development. Routledge, London, pp81–105
Lane, S N and Richards, K S R (1997) ‘Linking river channel form and process: time, space and causality revisited’, Earth Surface Processes and Landforms, vol 22, pp249–260
Lindemann R L (1942) ‘The trophic-dynamic aspect of ecology’, Ecology, vol 23, pp399–418
Lindsay, W K (1987) ’ integrating parks and pastoralists: some lessons from Amboseli’ in D M Anderson and R H Grove (eds) Conservation in Africa: people, policies and practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp149–168
Livingstone, D N (1995) ‘The polity of nature: representation, virtue, strategy’, Ecumene, vol 2(4), pp353–377
Mace, R (1991) ‘Overgrazing overstated’, Nature, vol 349, pp280–281, 24 January Marsh, G P (1864) Man and Nature; or, physical geography as modified by human action.
Scribners, New York; Sampson Low, London (reprinted Harvard University Press, 1965)
May, R M (1989) ‘Levels of organisation in ecology’ in J M Cherrett (ed) Ecological Concepts: the contribution of ecology to an understanding of the natural world. Blackwell, Oxford (for the British Ecological Society), pp339–363
McHarg, I L (1969) Design with Nature. Natural History Press, Garden City, New York McIntosh, R P (1985) The Background of Ecology: concept and theory. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge
Neumann, R P (1998) Imposing Wilderness: struggles over livelihood and nature preservation in Africa. University of California Press, Berkeley
Nicholson, E M (1957) Britain’s Nature Reserves. Country Life Limited, London Nicholson, E M (1970) The Environmental Revolution: a guide to the new masters of the world.
Hodder and Stoughton, London (Penguin edition 1972)
Pahl-Wostl, C (1995) The Dynamic Nature of Ecosystems: chaos and order intertwined. Wiley, Chichester
Pearsall, W H (1964) ‘The development of ecology in Britain’, Journal of Ecology, vol 52, pp1–12
Perrow, M R and Davy, A J (2002) (eds) Handbook of Ecological Restoration. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Reisner, M (1986) Cadillac Desert: the American West and its disappearing waters. Peregrine Books, New York
Rodwell, J, S (ed) (1991) British Plant Communities, volume 1: woodlands and scrub. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, for the Nature Conservancy Council
Royal Society for the Protection of Birds (RSPB) (1994) The New Rivers and Wildlife Handbook, second edition. Royal Society for the Protection of Birds, Sandy
Sandford, S (1983) Management of Pastoral Development in the Third World. Wiley, Chichester
Sheail, J (1976) Nature in Trust: the history of nature conservation in Great Britain. Blackie, Glasgow
Sheail, J (1981) Rural Conservation in Inter-War Britain. Clarendon Press, Oxford Sheail, J (1987) Seventy-Five Years of Ecology: the British Ecological Society. Blackwell
Scientific, Oxford
Sheail, J (1995) ‘From aspiration to implementation – the establishment of the first national nature reserves in Britain’, Landscape Research, vol 21(1), pp37–54
Sinclair, A R and Fryxell, J M (1985) ‘The Sahel of Africa: ecology of a disaster’,
Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol 63, pp987–994
Steward T A, Pickett, V, Parker, T and Feidler, P L (1992) ‘The new paradigm in ecology: implications for conservation biology above the species level’ in P L Feidler and S K Jain (eds) Conservation Biology: the theory and practice of nature conservation, preservation and management. Chapman and Hall, London, pp65–88
Sutherland, W J and Hill, D A (1995) Managing Habitats for Conservation, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Swift, J (1982) ‘The future of African hunter-gatherer and pastoral people in Africa’, Development and Change, vol 13, pp159-181
Swift, J (1996) ‘Desertification narratives; winners and losers’ in M Leach and R Mearns (eds) The Lie of the Land: challenging received wisdom on the African environment. James Currey Heinemann, London, pp73–90
Tansley A G (1911) Types of British Vegetation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Tansley A G (1935) ‘The use and abuse of vegetational terms’, Ecology, vol 14(3),
pp284–307
Tansley A G (1939) ‘British ecology in the past quarter century: the plant community and the ecosystem’, Journal of Ecology, vol 27, pp513–530
Turner, F (1987) ‘The self-effacing art: restoration as imitation of nature’ in W R Jordan III, M E Gilpin and J D Aber (eds) Restoration Ecology: a synthetic approach to ecological research. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp47–50
Waller, R D (1988) ‘Emutai: crisis and response in Maasailand (1884–1904)’, in D Johnson and D M Anderson (eds) The Ecology of Survival. Lester Crook, London, pp73–112
Wallis DeVries, M F, Bakker, J P and Van Wieren, S E (eds) (2001) Grazing and Conservation Management. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht
Warren, A (1996) ‘Desertification’ in W M Adams, A S Goudie and A Orme (eds) The Physical Geography of Africa. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp342–355
Werrity, A, McManus J, Brazier, V and Gordon, J (1994) ‘Conserving our dynamic and static geomorphological heritage’, Earth Heritage, vol 1, pp16–17
Williams-Ellis, A and Williams-Ellis, C (1951) Headlong Down the Years: a tale of today. Liverpool University Press, Liverpool
Worster, D (1985) Rivers of Empire. Norton and Co, New York
Worster, D (1994) ‘Nature and the disorder of history’, Environmental History Review, vol 18(2), pp1–16 (reprinted in M Soulé and G Lease (eds) (1995) Reinventing Nature: responses to postmodern deconstruction. Island Press, Washington, DC)
Zoest, J van (1992) ‘Gambling with nature? A new paradigm of nature and its consequences for nature management strategy’ in R W G Carter, T G F Curtis and M J Sheehy-Skeffington (eds) Coastal Dunes. Balkema, Rotterdam, pp503–514
Unofficial librarian of vegan and socialist movement media.
PhiloVegan Wiki: https://tinyurl.com/y7jc6kh6
Vegan Video Library: https://tinyurl.com/yb3udm8x
Ishkah YouTube: https://youtube.com/Ishkah
Post Reply